Condorcet criterion
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

An
electoral system An electoral system or voting system is a set of rules that determine how elections and referendums are conducted and how their results are determined. Electoral systems are used in politics to elect governments, while non-political elections ma ...
satisfies the Condorcet winner criterion () if it always chooses the Condorcet winner when one exists. The candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidatesthat is, a candidate preferred by more voters than any othersis the Condorcet winner, although Condorcet winners do not exist in all cases. It is sometimes simply referred to as the "Condorcet criterion", though it is very different from the "
Condorcet loser criterion In single-winner voting system theory, the Condorcet loser criterion (CLC) is a measure for differentiating voting systems. It implies the majority loser criterion but does not imply the Condorcet winner criterion. A voting system complying wi ...
". Any voting method conforming to the Condorcet winner criterion is known as a
Condorcet method A Condorcet method (; ) is an election method that elects the candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates, that is, a candidate preferred by more voters than any others, whenever ...
. The Condorcet winner is the person who would win a two-candidate election against each of the other candidates in a
plurality vote Plurality voting refers to electoral systems in which a candidate, or candidates, who poll more than any other counterpart (that is, receive a plurality), are elected. In systems based on single-member districts, it elects just one member per ...
. For a set of candidates, the Condorcet winner is always the same regardless of the voting system in question, and can be discovered by using pairwise counting on voters' ranked preferences. A Condorcet winner will not always exist in a given set of votes, which is known as Condorcet's voting paradox; however, there will always be a smallest group of candidates such that more voters prefer anyone in the group over anyone outside of the group in a head-to-head matchup, which is known as the
Smith set In voting systems, the Smith set, named after John H. Smith, but also known as the top cycle, or as Generalized Top-Choice Assumption (GETCHA), is the smallest non-empty set of candidates in a particular election such that each member defeats ever ...
. When voters identify candidates on a 1-dimensional, e.g., left-to-right axis and always prefer candidates closer to themselves, a Condorcet winner always exists. Real political positions are multi-dimensional, however, which can lead to circular societal preferences with no Condorcet winner. These terms are named after the 18th-century mathematician and philosopher Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Caritat, the Marquis de Condorcet. The concept had previously been proposed by Ramon Llull in the 13th century, though this was not known until the 2001 discovery of his lost manuscripts.


Example

Suppose the following matrix of pairwise preferences exists for an election: where the left axis labels of the above matrix indicate the runner and the upper axis labels indicate the opponent and votes in a pairwise contest can be found by comparing correspondences of runner/opponent. For example, to calculate the number of votes won by B in a head-to-head contest against A, the middle cell of the leftmost column indicates that B wins 305 votes against A, while the corresponding top cell in the middle column indicates that A gets 186 votes against B; therefore, B beats A in a two-candidate, pairwise election with a total of 305 votes to 186. In the example matrix above, B is the Condorcet winner, because they beat A and C in head-to-head elections.


Proof of violation of fairness

Note that the quantity of votes might not strongly favor a candidate, but that candidates only need to win the most number of contests in order to be a Condorcet winner. In the above example, B beats two other candidates (there are two green boxes indicating victory for B in the middle row) and A beats one. But the total margin by which a Condorcet winner is irrelevant: a Condorcet winner could win enough contests to be the Condorcet winner by just one vote each, while another candidate might win more votes but fewer contests. Condorcet-consistent voting systems can also, in rare cases, exhibit a preference cycle or paradox, although the circumstances that would cause this has not been known to occur yet in a governmental election using ranked ballots.


Relation to other criteria

The Condorcet criterion implies the
majority criterion The majority criterion is a single-winner voting system criterion, used to compare such systems. The criterion states that "if one candidate is ranked first by a majority (more than 50%) of voters, then that candidate must win". Some methods that ...
; that is, any system that satisfies the former will satisfy the latter. It further implies the mutual majority criterion whenever there is a Condorcet winner; the Smith criterion, which is a generalization of the Condorcet criterion, always implies the mutual majority criterion; not all Condorcet methods pass the Smith criterion. The Condorcet criterion is incompatible with the
later-no-harm criterion The later-no-harm criterion is a voting system criterion formulated by Douglas Woodall. Woodall defined the criterion as " ding a later preference to a ballot should not harm any candidate already listed." For example, a ranked voting method in w ...
, the favorite betrayal criterion, the
participation criterion The participation criterion is a voting system criterion. Voting systems that fail the participation criterion are said to exhibit the no show paradox and allow a particularly unusual strategy of tactical voting: abstaining from an election can he ...
, and the
consistency criterion A voting system is consistent if, whenever the electorate is divided (arbitrarily) into several parts and elections in those parts garner the same result, then an election of the entire electorate also garners that result. Smith calls this property ...
. The Condorcet criterion satisfies the following criterion with some similarity to independence of irrelevant alternatives: removing losing candidates from the election can't change the result whenever there is a Condorcet winner. In addition, adding candidates who are pairwise beaten by the Condorcet winner can't change the winner when there is a Condorcet winner. (These two properties are related to, and implied by, the Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives criterion.) The Condorcet winner criterion is different from the
Condorcet loser criterion In single-winner voting system theory, the Condorcet loser criterion (CLC) is a measure for differentiating voting systems. It implies the majority loser criterion but does not imply the Condorcet winner criterion. A voting system complying wi ...
. A system complying with the Condorcet loser criterion will never allow a ''Condorcet loser'' to win; that is a candidate who can be defeated in a head-to-head competition against each other candidate


Compliance of methods


Complying methods

The following methods satisfy the Condorcet criterion: *
Black Black is a color which results from the absence or complete absorption of visible light. It is an achromatic color, without hue, like white and grey. It is often used symbolically or figuratively to represent darkness. Black and white ...
* Copeland *
Dodgson's method Dodgson's method is an electoral system proposed by the author, mathematician and logician Charles Dodgson, better known as Lewis Carroll Charles Lutwidge Dodgson (; 27 January 1832 – 14 January 1898), better known by his pen name Lewis ...
* Kemeny-Young * Minimax *
Nanson's method The Borda count electoral system can be combined with an instant-runoff procedure to create hybrid election methods that are called Nanson method and Baldwin method (also called Total Vote Runoff or TVR). Both methods are designed to satisfy the ...
*
Ranked pairs Ranked pairs (sometimes abbreviated "RP") or the Tideman method is an electoral system developed in 1987 by Nicolaus Tideman that selects a single winner using votes that express preferences. The ranked-pairs procedure can also be used to create ...
* Schulze * Smith/IRV * Smith/minimax *
CPO-STV CPO-STV, or the Comparison of Pairs of Outcomes by the Single Transferable Vote, is a ranked voting system designed to achieve proportional representation. It is a more sophisticated variant of the Single Transferable Vote (STV) system, designed ...


Non-complying methods

The following methods do not satisfy the Condorcet criterion. (This statement requires qualification in some cases: see the individual subsections.) * Borda count *
Bucklin voting Bucklin voting is a class of voting methods that can be used for single-member and multi-member districts. As in highest median rules like the majority judgment, the Bucklin winner will be one of the candidates with the highest median ranking ...
* Instant-runoff voting *
Majority judgment Majority judgment (MJ) is a single-winner voting system proposed in 2007 by Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki. It is a highest median rule, i.e., a cardinal voting system that elects the candidate with the highest median rating. Unlike other v ...
*
Plurality voting Plurality voting refers to electoral systems in which a candidate, or candidates, who poll more than any other counterpart (that is, receive a plurality), are elected. In systems based on single-member districts, it elects just one member pe ...
* Approval voting * Range voting * Coombs rule


Borda count

Borda count is a voting system in which voters rank the candidates in an order of preference. Points are given for the position of a candidate in a voter's rank order. The candidate with the most points wins. The Borda count does not comply with the Condorcet criterion in the following case. Consider an election consisting of five voters and three alternatives, in which three voters prefer A to B and B to C, while two of the voters prefer B to C and C to A. The fact that A is preferred by three of the five voters to all other alternatives makes it a Condorcet Winner. However the Borda count awards 2 points for 1st choice, 1 point for second and 0 points for third. Thus, from three voters who prefer A, A receives 6 points (3 × 2), and 0 points from the other two voters, for a total of 6 points. B receives 3 points (3 × 1) from the three voters who prefer A to B to C, and 4 points (2 × 2) from the other two voters who prefer B to C to A. With 7 points, B is the Borda winner.


Bucklin voting

Bucklin is a ranked voting method that was used in some elections during the early 20th century in the
United States The United States of America (U.S.A. or USA), commonly known as the United States (U.S. or US) or America, is a country primarily located in North America. It consists of 50 states, a federal district, five major unincorporated territori ...
. The election proceeds in rounds, one rank at a time, until a majority is reached. Initially, votes are counted for all candidates ranked in first place; if no candidate has a majority, votes are recounted with candidates in both first and second place. This continues until one candidate has a total number of votes that is more than half the number of voters. Because multiple candidates per vote may be considered at one time, it is possible for more than one candidate to achieve a majority.


Instant-runoff voting

Instant-runoff voting (IRV) is a method (like Borda count) which requires each voter to rank the candidates. Unlike the Borda count, IRV uses a process of elimination to assign each voter's ballot to their first choice among a dwindling list of remaining candidates until one candidate receives an outright majority of ballots. It does not comply with the Condorcet criterion. Consider, for example, the following vote count of preferences with three candidates : * A > B > C: 35 * C > B > A: 34 * B > C > A: 31 In this case, B is preferred to A by 65 votes to 35, and B is preferred to C by 66 to 34, hence B is strongly preferred to both A and C. B must then win according to the Condorcet criterion. Using the rules of IRV, B is ranked first by the fewest voters and is eliminated, and then C wins with the transferred votes from B. Note that 65 voters, a majority, prefer either candidate B or C over A; since IRV passes the mutual majority criterion, it guarantees one of B and C must win. If candidate A, an irrelevant alternative under IRV, was not running, a majority of voters would consider B their 1st choice, and IRV's mutual majority compliance would thus ensure B wins; in this way, IRV's failure of the Condorcet criterion here also implies a spoiler effect. In cases where there is a Condorcet Winner, and where IRV does not choose that candidate, a simple majority would by definition prefer the Condorcet Winner over the IRV winner. This anomalous case was demonstrated in the 2009 mayoral election of Burlington Vermont.


Majority judgment

Majority judgment is a system in which the voter gives all candidates a rating out of a predetermined set (e.g. ). The winner of the election would be the candidate with the best median rating. Consider an election with three candidates A, B, C. * 35 voters rate candidate A "excellent", B "fair", and C "poor", * 34 voters rate candidate C "excellent", B "fair", and A "poor", and * 31 voters rate candidate B "excellent", C "fair", and A "poor". B is preferred to A by 65 votes to 35, and B is preferred to C by 66 to 34. Hence, B is the Condorcet winner. But B only gets the median rating "fair", while C has the median rating "good" and hereby C is chosen winner by Majority Judgment.


Plurality voting

With plurality voting, the full set of voter preferences is not recorded on the ballot and so cannot be deduced therefrom (e.g. following a real election). Under the assumption that no tactical voting takes place, i.e. that all voters vote for their first preference, it is easy to construct an example which fails the Condorcet criterion. Consider an election in which 30% of the voters prefer candidate A to candidate B to candidate C and vote for A, 30% of the voters prefer C to A to B and vote for C, and 40% of the voters prefer B to A to C and vote for B. Candidate B would win (with 40% of the vote) even though A would be the Condorcet winner, beating B 60% to 40%, and C 70% to 30%. The assumption of no tactical voting is also used to evaluate other systems; however, the assumption may be far less plausible with plurality precisely because plurality accommodates no other way for subsidiary preferences to be taken into account.


Approval voting

Approval voting is a system in which the voter can approve of (or vote for) any number of candidates on a ballot. Depending on which strategies voters use, the Condorcet criterion may be violated. Consider an election in which 70% of the voters prefer candidate A to candidate B to candidate C, while 30% of the voters prefer C to B to A. If every voter votes for their top two favorites, Candidate B would win (with 100% approval) even though A would be the Condorcet winner. Note that this failure of Approval depends upon a particular generalization of the Condorcet criterion, which may not be accepted by all voting theorists. Other generalizations, such as a "votes-only" generalization that makes no reference to voter preferences, may result in a different analysis. Also, if all voters have perfect information about each other's motivations, and a single Condorcet winner exists, then that candidate will win under the Nash equilibrium.


Range voting

Range voting is a system in which the voter gives all candidates a score on a predetermined scale (e.g. from 0 to 9). The winner of the election is the candidate with the highest total score. Range voting doesn't satisfy the Condorcet criterion. Consider an election with three voters and three candidates with the following range votes: In pluralistic head-to-head elections, two voters prefer A to B, and all three prefer both A and B to C, making A the Condorcet winner. However, candidate B is the range winner with 12 points compared to 11 points for A. Range voting satisfies the Condorcet criterion as long as voters score candidates in the head-to-head elections as they do in the full election. For example, let's say three voters vote for three candidates (A,B,C) as follows: The second candidate is the Condorcet winner and the winner of the normal election with 12 to 10 and 0 points. In the case where all voters are voting strategically, range voting is equivalent to approval voting, and any Condorcet winner will win because of the Nash equilibrium as mentioned above. However, if voters change their voting strategy from honest to strategic ''only'' for the head-to-head elections, then range voting does not satisfy Condorcet. For the same example shown above, the head-to-head elections involving A would look like this: Since in both cases, A would be the winner, the Condorcet winner is A, but B still wins the full election. Some, like the authors of rangevoting.org, say that defining the Condorcet criterion in this way makes the criterion not always desirable. If the winners of the head-to-head contests were determined by range voting rules rather than pluralistic voting, range voting would satisfy Condorcet.


STAR voting

STAR voting is a variant of score voting with an additional runoff step, where the most preferred of the top-two rated candidates wins. STAR voting does not satisfy the Condorcet criterion. Nevertheless, provided the Condorcet winner is one of the top two rated candidates, it wins the election by virtue of the runoff step being based solely on the ranked preferences between the two. The following example is an election with 100 voters and 3 candidates : * 45 voters voting: A=5 B=1 C=0 (Preferences: A>B>C) * 40 voters voting: A=0 B=1 C=5 (Preferences: C>B>A) * 15 voters voting: A=1 B=5 C=0 (Preferences: B>A>C) Under STAR voting, the total ratings are A=240, B=160, C=200, thus A and C are chosen as finalists and the ballots are read again, taking only preferences between the two finalists into account. From the given ballots, we have that 60% of voters prefer A over C, thus A is the STAR voting winner. However, from the preference information alone, we see that B is preferred over A by 55% of voters, and over C by 60% of voters. This makes B the Condorcet winner, and thus STAR voting has failed to elect it. Proponents of STAR voting argue that this can be a superior result given the extra information available in rated ballots, as the ranking information alone is insufficient information to distinguish between a second-choice ranking being almost as good as a voter's favorite, or almost as bad as their worst case scenario.: "A ranked ballot doesn't allow voters to express their level of support, and thus a 2nd choice ranking could be almost as good as a voter's favorite or almost as bad as their worst case scenario." The above example illustrates such situation, in which the Condorcet winner can be rated very poorly by 85% of voters.


Further reading

* * *


See also

*
Condorcet loser criterion In single-winner voting system theory, the Condorcet loser criterion (CLC) is a measure for differentiating voting systems. It implies the majority loser criterion but does not imply the Condorcet winner criterion. A voting system complying wi ...
*
Condorcet method A Condorcet method (; ) is an election method that elects the candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates, that is, a candidate preferred by more voters than any others, whenever ...
* Multiwinner voting - contains information on some multiwinner variants of the Condorcet criterion.


References

{{voting systems Electoral system criteria