HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (math ...
, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the
first-order language First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
of fields that is true for the
complex number In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted , called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation i^= -1; every complex number can be expressed in the fo ...
s is also true for any
algebraically closed field In mathematics, a field is algebraically closed if every non-constant polynomial in (the univariate polynomial ring with coefficients in ) has a root in . Examples As an example, the field of real numbers is not algebraically closed, because ...
of
characteristic 0 In mathematics, the characteristic of a ring , often denoted , is defined to be the smallest number of times one must use the ring's multiplicative identity (1) in a sum to get the additive identity (0). If this sum never reaches the additive id ...
.


History

An incipient form of a transfer principle was described by
Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm (von) Leibniz . ( – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat. He is one of the most prominent figures in both the history of philosophy and the history of ma ...
under the name of "the
Law of Continuity The law of continuity is a heuristic principle introduced by Gottfried Leibniz based on earlier work by Nicholas of Cusa and Johannes Kepler. It is the principle that "whatever succeeds for the finite, also succeeds for the infinite". Kepler used ...
". Here
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a quantity that is closer to zero than any standard real number, but that is not zero. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally re ...
s are expected to have the "same" properties as appreciable numbers. The transfer principle can also be viewed as a rigorous formalization of the principle of permanence. Similar tendencies are found in
Cauchy Baron Augustin-Louis Cauchy (, ; ; 21 August 178923 May 1857) was a French mathematician, engineer, and physicist who made pioneering contributions to several branches of mathematics, including mathematical analysis and continuum mechanics. He w ...
, who used infinitesimals to define both the continuity of functions (in
Cours d'Analyse ''Cours d'Analyse de l’École Royale Polytechnique; I.re Partie. Analyse algébrique'' is a seminal textbook in infinitesimal calculus published by Augustin-Louis Cauchy in 1821. The article follows the translation by Bradley and Sandifer in de ...
) and a form of the
Dirac delta function In mathematics, the Dirac delta distribution ( distribution), also known as the unit impulse, is a generalized function or distribution over the real numbers, whose value is zero everywhere except at zero, and whose integral over the enti ...
. In 1955, Jerzy Łoś proved the transfer principle for any
hyperreal number In mathematics, the system of hyperreal numbers is a way of treating infinite and infinitesimal (infinitely small but non-zero) quantities. The hyperreals, or nonstandard reals, *R, are an extension of the real numbers R that contains numbers ...
system. Its most common use is in
Abraham Robinson Abraham Robinson (born Robinsohn; October 6, 1918 – April 11, 1974) was a mathematician who is most widely known for development of nonstandard analysis, a mathematically rigorous system whereby infinitesimal and infinite numbers were reincorp ...
's
nonstandard analysis The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using (ε, δ)-definitio ...
of the
hyperreal number In mathematics, the system of hyperreal numbers is a way of treating infinite and infinitesimal (infinitely small but non-zero) quantities. The hyperreals, or nonstandard reals, *R, are an extension of the real numbers R that contains numbers ...
s, where the transfer principle states that any sentence expressible in a certain formal language that is true of
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every ...
s is also true of hyperreal numbers.


Transfer principle for the hyperreals

The transfer principle concerns the logical relation between the properties of the real numbers R, and the properties of a larger field denoted *R called the
hyperreal number In mathematics, the system of hyperreal numbers is a way of treating infinite and infinitesimal (infinitely small but non-zero) quantities. The hyperreals, or nonstandard reals, *R, are an extension of the real numbers R that contains numbers ...
s. The field *R includes, in particular, infinitesimal ("infinitely small") numbers, providing a rigorous mathematical realisation of a project initiated by Leibniz. The idea is to express analysis over R in a suitable language of
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of forma ...
, and then point out that this language applies equally well to *R. This turns out to be possible because at the set-theoretic level, the propositions in such a language are interpreted to apply only to internal sets rather than to all sets. As
Robinson Robinson may refer to: People and names * Robinson (name) Fictional characters * Robinson Crusoe, the main character, and title of a novel by Daniel Defoe, published in 1719 Geography * Robinson projection, a map projection used since the 1960 ...
put it, ''the sentences of he theoryare interpreted in *R in Henkin's sense.''Robinson, A. The metaphysics of the calculus, in Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics, ed. Lakatos (Amsterdam: North Holland), pp. 28–46, 1967. Reprinted in the 1979 Collected Works. Page 29. The theorem to the effect that each proposition valid over R, is also valid over *R, is called the transfer principle. There are several different versions of the transfer principle, depending on what model of nonstandard mathematics is being used. In terms of model theory, the transfer principle states that a map from a standard model to a nonstandard model is an
elementary embedding In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one often ...
(an embedding preserving the
truth value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Computing In some pro ...
s of all statements in a language), or sometimes a ''bounded'' elementary embedding (similar, but only for statements with
bounded quantifier In the study of formal theories in mathematical logic, bounded quantifiers (a.k.a. restricted quantifiers) are often included in a formal language in addition to the standard quantifiers "∀" and "∃". Bounded quantifiers differ from "∀" and ...
s). The transfer principle appears to lead to contradictions if it is not handled correctly. For example, since the hyperreal numbers form a non- Archimedean
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. The basic example of an ordered field is the field of real numbers, and every Dedekind-complete ordered fiel ...
and the reals form an Archimedean ordered field, the property of being Archimedean ("every positive real is larger than 1/n for some positive integer n") seems at first sight not to satisfy the transfer principle. The statement "every positive hyperreal is larger than 1/n for some positive integer n" is false; however the correct interpretation is "every positive hyperreal is larger than 1/n for some positive hyperinteger n". In other words, the hyperreals appear to be Archimedean to an internal observer living in the nonstandard universe, but appear to be non-Archimedean to an external observer outside the universe. A freshman-level accessible formulation of the transfer principle is Keisler's book '' Elementary Calculus: An Infinitesimal Approach''.


Example

Every real x satisfies the inequality x \geq \lfloor x \rfloor, where \lfloor \,\cdot\, \rfloor is the
integer part In mathematics and computer science, the floor function is the function that takes as input a real number , and gives as output the greatest integer less than or equal to , denoted or . Similarly, the ceiling function maps to the least int ...
function. By a typical application of the transfer principle, every hyperreal x satisfies the inequality x \geq ^\! \lfloor x \rfloor, where ^\! \lfloor \,\cdot\, \rfloor is the natural extension of the integer part function. If x is infinite, then the hyperinteger ^\! \lfloor x \rfloor is infinite, as well.


Generalizations of the concept of number

Historically, the concept of
number A number is a mathematical object used to count, measure, and label. The original examples are the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, and so forth. Numbers can be represented in language with number words. More universally, individual number ...
has been repeatedly generalized. The addition of 0 to the natural numbers \mathbb was a major intellectual accomplishment in its time. The addition of negative integers to form \mathbb already constituted a departure from the realm of immediate experience to the realm of mathematical models. The further extension, the rational numbers \mathbb, is more familiar to a layperson than their completion \mathbb, partly because the reals do not correspond to any physical reality (in the sense of measurement and computation) different from that represented by \mathbb. Thus, the notion of an irrational number is meaningless to even the most powerful floating-point computer. The necessity for such an extension stems not from physical observation but rather from the internal requirements of mathematical coherence. The infinitesimals entered mathematical discourse at a time when such a notion was required by mathematical developments at the time, namely the emergence of what became known as the
infinitesimal calculus Calculus, originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the calculus of infinitesimals", is the mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of ari ...
. As already mentioned above, the mathematical justification for this latest extension was delayed by three centuries. Keisler wrote: :"In discussing the real line we remarked that we have no way of knowing what a line in physical space is really like. It might be like the hyperreal line, the real line, or neither. However, in applications of the calculus, it is helpful to imagine a line in physical space as a hyperreal line." The
self-consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent ...
development of the hyperreals turned out to be possible if every true
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
statement that uses basic arithmetic (the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
s, plus, times, comparison) and quantifies only over the real numbers was assumed to be true in a reinterpreted form if we presume that it quantifies over hyperreal numbers. For example, we can state that for every real number there is another number greater than it: : \forall x \in \mathbb \quad \exists y \in\mathbb\quad x < y. The same will then also hold for hyperreals: : \forall x \in ^\star\mathbb \quad \exists y \in ^\star\mathbb\quad x < y. Another example is the statement that if you add 1 to a number you get a bigger number: : \forall x \in \mathbb \quad x < x+1 which will also hold for hyperreals: : \forall x \in ^\star\mathbb \quad x < x+1. The correct general statement that formulates these equivalences is called the transfer principle. Note that, in many formulas in analysis, quantification is over higher-order objects such as functions and sets, which makes the transfer principle somewhat more subtle than the above examples suggest.


Differences between R and *R

The transfer principle however doesn't mean that R and *R have identical behavior. For instance, in *R there exists an element ''ω'' such that : 1<\omega, \quad 1+1<\omega, \quad 1+1+1<\omega, \quad 1+1+1+1<\omega, \ldots but there is no such number in R. This is possible because the nonexistence of this number cannot be expressed as a first order statement of the above type. A hyperreal number like ''ω'' is called infinitely large; the reciprocals of the infinitely large numbers are the infinitesimals. The hyperreals *R form an
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. The basic example of an ordered field is the field of real numbers, and every Dedekind-complete ordered fiel ...
containing the reals R as a subfield. Unlike the reals, the hyperreals do not form a standard
metric space In mathematics, a metric space is a set together with a notion of '' distance'' between its elements, usually called points. The distance is measured by a function called a metric or distance function. Metric spaces are the most general setti ...
, but by virtue of their order they carry an order
topology In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ...
.


Constructions of the hyperreals

The hyperreals can be developed either axiomatically or by more constructively oriented methods. The essence of the axiomatic approach is to assert (1) the existence of at least one infinitesimal number, and (2) the validity of the transfer principle. In the following subsection we give a detailed outline of a more constructive approach. This method allows one to construct the hyperreals if given a set-theoretic object called an
ultrafilter In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a maximal filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter o ...
, but the ultrafilter itself cannot be explicitly constructed.
Vladimir Kanovei Vladimir G. Kanovei (born 1951) is a Russian mathematician working at the Institute for Information Transmission Problems in Moscow, Russia. His interests include mathematical logic and foundations, as well as mathematical history. Selected pu ...
and Shelah give a construction of a definable, countably saturated elementary extension of the structure consisting of the reals and all finitary relations on it. In its most general form, transfer is a bounded
elementary embedding In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one often ...
between structures.


Statement

The
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. The basic example of an ordered field is the field of real numbers, and every Dedekind-complete ordered fiel ...
*R of nonstandard real numbers properly includes the
real Real may refer to: Currencies * Brazilian real (R$) * Central American Republic real * Mexican real * Portuguese real * Spanish real * Spanish colonial real Music Albums * ''Real'' (L'Arc-en-Ciel album) (2000) * ''Real'' (Bright album) (2010) ...
field R. Like all ordered fields that properly include R, this field is non-Archimedean. It means that some members ''x'' ≠ 0 of *R are
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a quantity that is closer to zero than any standard real number, but that is not zero. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally re ...
, i.e., : \underbrace_ < 1 \text n. The only infinitesimal in ''R'' is 0. Some other members of *R, the reciprocals ''y'' of the nonzero infinitesimals, are infinite, i.e., : \underbrace_<\left, y\ \text n. The underlying set of the field *R is the image of R under a mapping ''A''  *''A'' from subsets ''A'' of R to subsets of *R. In every case : A \subseteq , with equality if and only if ''A'' is finite. Sets of the form *''A'' for some \scriptstyle A\,\subseteq\,\mathbb are called standard subsets of *R. The standard sets belong to a much larger class of subsets of *R called internal sets. Similarly each function : f:A\rightarrow\mathbb extends to a function : : \rightarrow ; these are called standard functions, and belong to the much larger class of internal functions. Sets and functions that are not internal are external. The importance of these concepts stems from their role in the following proposition and is illustrated by the examples that follow it. The transfer principle: * Suppose a proposition that is true of *R can be expressed via functions of finitely many variables (e.g. (''x'', ''y'')  ''x'' + ''y''), relations among finitely many variables (e.g. ''x'' ≤ ''y''), finitary logical connectives such as and, or, not, if...then..., and the quantifiers :: \forall x\in\mathbb\text\exists x\in\mathbb. : For example, one such proposition is :: \forall x\in\mathbb \ \exists y\in\mathbb \ x+y=0. : Such a proposition is true in R if and only if it is true in *R when the quantifier :: \forall x \in : replaces :: \forall x\in\mathbb, : and similarly for \exists. * Suppose a proposition otherwise expressible as simply as those considered above mentions some particular sets \scriptstyle A\,\subseteq\,\mathbb. Such a proposition is true in R if and only if it is true in *R with each such "''A''" replaced by the corresponding *''A''. Here are two examples: :* The set ::: ,1\ast = \^\ast :: must be ::: \, :: including not only members of R between 0 and 1 inclusive, but also members of *R between 0 and 1 that differ from those by infinitesimals. To see this, observe that the sentence ::: \forall x\in\mathbb \ (x\in ,1\text 0\leq x \leq 1) :: is true in R, and apply the transfer principle. :* The set *N must have no upper bound in *R (since the sentence expressing the non-existence of an upper bound of N in R is simple enough for the transfer principle to apply to it) and must contain ''n'' + 1 if it contains ''n'', but must not contain anything between ''n'' and ''n'' + 1. Members of ::: \setminus \mathbb :: are "infinite integers".) * Suppose a proposition otherwise expressible as simply as those considered above contains the quantifier :: \forall A\subseteq\mathbb\dots\text\exists A\subseteq\mathbb\dots\ . : Such a proposition is true in R if and only if it is true in *R after the changes specified above and the replacement of the quantifiers with :: forall \text A\subseteq\dots : and :: exists \text A\subseteq\dots .


Three examples

The appropriate setting for the hyperreal transfer principle is the world of ''internal'' entities. Thus, the well-ordering property of the natural numbers by transfer yields the fact that every internal subset of \mathbb has a least element. In this section internal sets are discussed in more detail. * Every nonempty ''internal'' subset of *R that has an upper bound in *R has a least upper bound in *R. Consequently the set of all infinitesimals is external. ** The well-ordering principle implies every nonempty ''internal'' subset of *N has a smallest member. Consequently the set ::: \setminus \mathbb :: of all infinite integers is external. * If ''n'' is an infinite integer, then the set (which is not standard) must be internal. To prove this, first observe that the following is trivially true: ::: \forall n\in\mathbb \ \exists A\subseteq\mathbb \ \forall x\in\mathbb \ \in A \text x \leq n :: Consequently ::: \forall n \in \ \exists \text A \subseteq \ \forall x \in \ \in A \text x\leq n * As with internal sets, so with internal functions: Replace :: \forall f : A \rightarrow \mathbb \dots : with :: \forall\text f: \rightarrow \dots : when applying the transfer principle, and similarly with \exists in place of \forall. : For example: If ''n'' is an infinite integer, then the complement of the image of any internal
one-to-one function In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositi ...
''ƒ'' from the infinite set into has exactly three members by the transfer principle. Because of the infiniteness of the domain, the complements of the images of one-to-one functions from the former set to the latter come in many sizes, but most of these functions are external. : This last example motivates an important definition: A *-finite (pronounced star-finite) subset of *R is one that can be placed in ''internal'' one-to-one correspondence with for some ''n'' ∈ *N.


See also

* '' Elementary Calculus: An Infinitesimal Approach'' * Principle of Permanence *
Generality of algebra In the history of mathematics, the generality of algebra was a phrase used by Augustin-Louis Cauchy to describe a method of argument that was used in the 18th century by mathematicians such as Leonhard Euler and Joseph-Louis Lagrange,. particularly ...


Notes


References

* * Hardy, Michael: "Scaled Boolean algebras". ''Adv. in Appl. Math.'' 29 (2002), no. 2, 243–292. * * * * Łoś, Jerzy (1955) Quelques remarques, théorèmes et problèmes sur les classes définissables d'algèbres. Mathematical interpretation of formal systems, pp. 98–113. North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam. * {{Logic Mathematical principles Model theory Nonstandard analysis