problem of multiple generality
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The problem of multiple generality names a failure in
traditional logic In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, ...
to describe certain intuitively valid inferences. For example, it is intuitively clear that if: :''Some cat is feared by every mouse'' then it follows logically that: :''All mice are afraid of at least one cat''. The syntax of
traditional logic In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, ...
(TL) permits exactly four sentence types: "All As are Bs", "No As are Bs", "Some As are Bs" and "Some As are not Bs". Each type is a quantified sentence containing exactly one quantifier. Since the sentences above each contain two quantifiers ('some' and 'every' in the first sentence and 'all' and 'at least one' in the second sentence), they cannot be adequately represented in TL. The best TL can do is to incorporate the second quantifier from each sentence into the second term, thus rendering the artificial-sounding terms 'feared-by-every-mouse' and 'afraid-of-at-least-one-cat'. This in effect "buries" these quantifiers, which are essential to the inference's validity, within the hyphenated terms. Hence the sentence "Some cat is feared by every mouse" is allotted the same
logical form In logic, logical form of a statement is a precisely-specified semantic version of that statement in a formal system. Informally, the logical form attempts to formalize a possibly ambiguous statement into a statement with a precise, unambiguou ...
as the sentence "Some cat is hungry". And so the logical form in TL is: :''Some As are Bs'' :''All Cs are Ds'' which is clearly invalid. The first logical calculus capable of dealing with such inferences was
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic ph ...
's ''
Begriffsschrift ''Begriffsschrift'' (German for, roughly, "concept-script") is a book on logic by Gottlob Frege, published in 1879, and the formal system set out in that book. ''Begriffsschrift'' is usually translated as ''concept writing'' or ''concept notatio ...
'' (1879), the ancestor of modern
predicate logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
, which dealt with quantifiers by means of variable bindings. Modestly, Frege did not argue that his logic was more expressive than extant logical calculi, but commentators on Frege's logic regard this as one of his key achievements. Using modern
predicate calculus Predicate or predication may refer to: * Predicate (grammar), in linguistics * Predication (philosophy) * several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic: **Predicate (mathematical logic) **Propositional function ** Finitary relation, ...
, we quickly discover that the statement is ambiguous. :''Some cat is feared by every mouse'' could mean ''(Some cat is feared) by every mouse'' (paraphrasable as ''Every mouse fears some cat''), i.e. :''For every mouse m, there exists a cat c, such that c is feared by m,'' :\forall m. \, (\, \text(m) \rightarrow \exists c. \, (\text(c) \land \text(m,c)) \, ) in which case the conclusion is trivial. But it could also mean ''Some cat is (feared by every mouse)'' (paraphrasable as '' There's a cat feared by all mice''), i.e. :''There exists one cat c, such that for every mouse m, c is feared by m.'' :\exists c. \, ( \, \text(c) \land \forall m. \, (\text(m) \rightarrow \text(m,c)) \, ) This example illustrates the importance of specifying the scope of such quantifiers as ''for all'' and ''there exists''.


Further reading

*
Patrick Suppes Patrick Colonel Suppes (; March 17, 1922 – November 17, 2014) was an American philosopher who made significant contributions to philosophy of science, the theory of measurement, the foundations of quantum mechanics, decision theory, psychology ...
, ''Introduction to Logic'', D. Van Nostrand, 1957, . * A. G. Hamilton, ''Logic for Mathematicians'', Cambridge University Press, 1978, . *
Paul Halmos Paul Richard Halmos ( hu, Halmos Pál; March 3, 1916 – October 2, 2006) was a Hungarian-born American mathematician and statistician who made fundamental advances in the areas of mathematical logic, probability theory, statistics, operator ...
and Steven Givant, ''Logic as Algebra'', MAA, 1998, . Term logic Classical logic {{logic-stub