HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of forma ...
, the compactness theorem states that a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
of
first-order In mathematics and other formal sciences, first-order or first order most often means either: * "linear" (a polynomial of degree at most one), as in first-order approximation and other calculus uses, where it is contrasted with "polynomials of hig ...
sentences has a model if and only if every finite
subset In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset of ...
of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (math ...
, as it provides a useful (but generally not effective) method for constructing models of any set of sentences that is finitely consistent. The compactness theorem for the
propositional calculus Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
is a consequence of Tychonoff's theorem (which says that the product of
compact space In mathematics, specifically general topology, compactness is a property that seeks to generalize the notion of a closed and bounded subset of Euclidean space by making precise the idea of a space having no "punctures" or "missing endpoints", i ...
s is compact) applied to compact Stone spaces, hence the theorem's name. Likewise, it is analogous to the finite intersection property characterization of compactness in
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called poin ...
s: a collection of
closed set In geometry, topology, and related branches of mathematics, a closed set is a set whose complement is an open set. In a topological space, a closed set can be defined as a set which contains all its limit points. In a complete metric space, a ...
s in a compact space has a non-empty
intersection In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, thei ...
if every finite subcollection has a non-empty intersection. The compactness theorem is one of the two key properties, along with the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-ord ...
, that is used in
Lindström's theorem In mathematical logic, Lindström's theorem (named after Swedish logician Per Lindström, who published it in 1969) states that first-order logic is the '' strongest logic'' (satisfying certain conditions, e.g. closure under classical negation) h ...
to characterize first-order logic. Although there are some generalizations of the compactness theorem to non-first-order logics, the compactness theorem itself does not hold in them, except for a very limited number of examples.


History

Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imm ...
proved the countable compactness theorem in 1930.
Anatoly Maltsev Anatoly Ivanovich Maltsev (also: Malcev, Mal'cev; Russian: Анато́лий Ива́нович Ма́льцев; 27 November N.S./14 November O.S. 1909, Moscow Governorate – 7 June 1967, Novosibirsk) was born in Misheronsky, near Moscow, an ...
proved the uncountable case in 1936.


Applications

The compactness theorem has many applications in model theory; a few typical results are sketched here.


Robinson's principle

The compactness theorem implies the following result, stated by Abraham Robinson in his 1949 dissertation.
Robinson's principle Robinsons or Robinson's may refer to: Businesses Department stores * Robinsons Malls, shopping mall and retail operator in the Philippines * Robinsons, former department store chain owned by Robinson & Co. in Singapore and Malaysia * Robinson D ...
: If a first-order sentence holds in every field of characteristic zero, then there exists a constant p such that the sentence holds for every field of characteristic larger than p. This can be seen as follows: suppose \varphi is a sentence that holds in every field of characteristic zero. Then its negation \lnot \varphi, together with the field axioms and the infinite sequence of sentences 1 + 1 \neq 0, \;\; 1 + 1 + 1 \neq 0, \; \ldots is not
satisfiable In mathematical logic, a formula is ''satisfiable'' if it is true under some assignment of values to its variables. For example, the formula x+3=y is satisfiable because it is true when x=3 and y=6, while the formula x+1=x is not satisfiable ove ...
(because there is no field of characteristic 0 in which \lnot \varphi holds, and the infinite sequence of sentences ensures any model would be a field of characteristic 0). Therefore, there is a finite subset A of these sentences that is not satisfiable. A must contain \lnot \varphi because otherwise it would be satisfiable. Because adding more sentences to A does not change unsatisfiability, we can assume that A contains the field axioms and, for some k, the first k sentences of the form 1 + 1 + \cdots + 1 \neq 0. Let B contain all the sentences of A except \lnot \varphi. Then any field with a characteristic greater than k is a model of B, and \lnot \varphi together with B is not satisfiable. This means that \varphi must hold in every model of B, which means precisely that \varphi holds in every field of characteristic greater than k. This completes the proof. The Lefschetz principle, one of the first examples of a transfer principle, extends this result. A first-order sentence \varphi in the language of rings is true in (or equivalently, in ) algebraically closed field of characteristic 0 (such as the
complex number In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted , called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation i^= -1; every complex number can be expressed in the fo ...
s for instance) if and only if there exist infinitely many primes p for which \varphi is true in algebraically closed field of characteristic p, in which case \varphi is true in algebraically closed fields of sufficiently large non-0 characteristic p. One consequence is the following special case of the
Ax–Grothendieck theorem In mathematics, the Ax–Grothendieck theorem is a result about injectivity and surjectivity of polynomials that was proved independently by James Ax and Alexander Grothendieck. The theorem is often given as this special case: If ''P'' is an inj ...
: all
injective In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositi ...
complex
polynomial In mathematics, a polynomial is an expression consisting of indeterminates (also called variables) and coefficients, that involves only the operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and positive-integer powers of variables. An exampl ...
s \Complex^n \to \Complex^n are
surjective In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function) is a function that every element can be mapped from element so that . In other words, every element of the function's codomain is the image of one element o ...
(indeed, it can even be shown that its inverse will also be a polynomial). In fact, the surjectivity conclusion remains true for any injective polynomial F^n \to F^n where F is a finite field or the algebraic closure of such a field.


Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem

A second application of the compactness theorem shows that any theory that has arbitrarily large finite models, or a single infinite model, has models of arbitrary large cardinality (this is the
Upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem Upward may refer to: Music * ''Upwards'' (album), a 2003 album British hip-hop artist Ty Organizations * Upward Bound, a federally funded educational program within the United States * Upward Bound High School, a school in Hartwick, New York * ...
). So for instance, there are nonstandard models of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearl ...
with uncountably many 'natural numbers'. To achieve this, let T be the initial theory and let \kappa be any
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. ...
. Add to the language of T one constant symbol for every element of \kappa. Then add to T a collection of sentences that say that the objects denoted by any two distinct constant symbols from the new collection are distinct (this is a collection of \kappa^2 sentences). Since every subset of this new theory is satisfiable by a sufficiently large finite model of T, or by any infinite model, the entire extended theory is satisfiable. But any model of the extended theory has cardinality at least \kappa.


Non-standard analysis

A third application of the compactness theorem is the construction of nonstandard models of the real numbers, that is, consistent extensions of the theory of the real numbers that contain "infinitesimal" numbers. To see this, let \Sigma be a first-order axiomatization of the theory of the real numbers. Consider the theory obtained by adding a new constant symbol \varepsilon to the language and adjoining to \Sigma the axiom \varepsilon > 0 and the axioms \varepsilon < \tfrac for all positive integers n. Clearly, the standard real numbers \R are a model for every finite subset of these axioms, because the real numbers satisfy everything in \Sigma and, by suitable choice of \varepsilon, can be made to satisfy any finite subset of the axioms about \varepsilon. By the compactness theorem, there is a model ^* \R that satisfies \Sigma and also contains an infinitesimal element \varepsilon. A similar argument, this time adjoining the axioms \omega > 0, \; \omega > 1, \ldots, etc., shows that the existence of numbers with infinitely large magnitudes cannot be ruled out by any axiomatization \Sigma of the reals. It can be shown that the hyperreal numbers ^* \R satisfy the transfer principle: a first-order sentence is true of \R if and only if it is true of ^* \R.


Proofs

One can prove the compactness theorem using Gödel's completeness theorem, which establishes that a set of sentences is satisfiable if and only if no contradiction can be proven from it. Since proofs are always finite and therefore involve only finitely many of the given sentences, the compactness theorem follows. In fact, the compactness theorem is equivalent to Gödel's completeness theorem, and both are equivalent to the
Boolean prime ideal theorem In mathematics, the Boolean prime ideal theorem states that ideals in a Boolean algebra can be extended to prime ideals. A variation of this statement for filters on sets is known as the ultrafilter lemma. Other theorems are obtained by cons ...
, a weak form of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
.See Hodges (1993). Gödel originally proved the compactness theorem in just this way, but later some "purely semantic" proofs of the compactness theorem were found; that is, proofs that refer to but not to . One of those proofs relies on ultraproducts hinging on the axiom of choice as follows: Proof: Fix a first-order language L, and let \Sigma be a collection of L-sentences such that every finite subcollection of L-sentences, i \subseteq \Sigma of it has a model \mathcal_i. Also let \prod_\mathcal_i be the direct product of the structures and I be the collection of finite subsets of \Sigma. For each i \in I, let A_i = \. The family of all of these sets A_i generates a proper filter, so there is an ultrafilter U containing all sets of the form A_i. Now for any formula \varphi in \Sigma: * the set A_ is in U * whenever j \in A_, then \varphi \in j, hence \varphi holds in \mathcal M_j * the set of all j with the property that \varphi holds in \mathcal M_j is a superset of A_, hence also in U Łoś's theorem now implies that \varphi holds in the ultraproduct \prod_ \mathcal_i/U. So this ultraproduct satisfies all formulas in \Sigma.


See also

* * * *


Notes


References

* * * * * * * * *


External links


Compactness Theorem
'' Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. {{Mathematical logic Mathematical logic Metatheorems Model theory Theorems in the foundations of mathematics