HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, more precisely in
measure theory In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures (length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as mass and probability of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many simila ...
, an atom is a measurable set which has positive measure and contains no set of smaller positive measure. A measure which has no atoms is called non-atomic or atomless.


Definition

Given a
measurable space In mathematics, a measurable space or Borel space is a basic object in measure theory. It consists of a set and a σ-algebra, which defines the subsets that will be measured. Definition Consider a set X and a σ-algebra \mathcal A on X. Then the ...
(X, \Sigma) and a measure \mu on that space, a set A\subset X in \Sigma is called an atom if \mu(A) > 0 and for any measurable subset B \subset A with \mu(B) < \mu(A) the set B has measure zero. If A is an atom, all the subsets in the \mu-equivalence class /math> of A are atoms, and /math> is called an atomic class. If \mu is a \sigma-finite measure, there are countably many atomic classes.


Examples

* Consider the set ''X'' = and let the sigma-algebra \Sigma be the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
of ''X''. Define the measure \mu of a set to be its
cardinality In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
, that is, the number of elements in the set. Then, each of the singletons , for ''i'' = 1, 2, ..., 9, 10 is an atom. * Consider the
Lebesgue measure In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the Lebesgue measure, named after French mathematician Henri Lebesgue, is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of ''n''-dimensional Euclidean space. For ''n'' = 1, 2, or 3, it coincides wi ...
on the
real line In elementary mathematics, a number line is a picture of a graduated straight line that serves as visual representation of the real numbers. Every point of a number line is assumed to correspond to a real number, and every real number to a po ...
. This measure has no atoms.


Atomic measures

A \sigma-finite measure \mu on a
measurable space In mathematics, a measurable space or Borel space is a basic object in measure theory. It consists of a set and a σ-algebra, which defines the subsets that will be measured. Definition Consider a set X and a σ-algebra \mathcal A on X. Then the ...
(X, \Sigma) is called atomic or purely atomic if every measurable set of positive measure contains an atom. This is equivalent to say that there is a
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers ...
partition of X formed by atoms up to a null set. The assumption of \sigma-finitude is essential. Consider otherwise the space (\mathbb,\mathcal(\Reals),\nu) where \nu denotes the counting measure. This space is atomic, with all atoms being the singletons, yet the space is not able to be partitioned into the disjoint union of countably many disjoint atoms, \bigcup_^\infty A_n and a null set N since the countable union of singletons is a countable set, and the
uncountability of the real numbers In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \mathfrak c (lowercase fraktur "c") or , \mathbb ...
shows that the complement N = \mathbb \setminus \bigcup_^\infty A_n would have to be uncountable, hence its \nu-measure would be infinite, in contradiction to it being a null set. The validity of the result for \sigma-finite spaces follows from the proof for finite measure spaces by observing that the countable union of countable unions is again a countable union, and that the countable unions of null sets are null.


Discrete measures

A \sigma-finite atomic measure \mu is called discrete if the intersection of the atoms of any atomic class is non empty. It is equivalent to say that \mu is the weighted sum of countably many Dirac measures, that is, there is a sequence x_1,x_2,... of points in X , and a sequence c_1,c_2,... of positive real numbers (the weights) such that \mu=\sum_^\infty c_k\delta_ , which means that \mu(A) = \sum_^\infty c_k\delta_(A) for every A\in\Sigma . We can chose each point x_k to be a common point of the atoms in the k -th atomic class. A discrete measure is atomic but the inverse implication fails: take X= ,1/math>, \Sigma the \sigma-algebra of countable and co-countable subsets, \mu=0 in countable subsets and \mu=1 in co-countable subsets. Then there is a single atomic class, the one formed by the co-countable subsets. The measure \mu is atomic but the intersection of the atoms in the unique atomic class is empty and \mu can't be put as a sum of Dirac measures. If every atom is equivalent to a singleton, \mu is discrete iff it is atomic. In this case the x_k above are the atomic singletons, so they are unique. Any finite measure in a separable metric space provided with the Borel sets satisfies this condition.


Non-atomic measures

A measure which has no atoms is called or a . In other words, a measure \mu is non-atomic if for any measurable set A with \mu(A) > 0 there exists a measurable subset B of A such that \mu(A) > \mu (B) > 0. A non-atomic measure with at least one positive value has an infinite number of distinct values, as starting with a set A with \mu(A) > 0 one can construct a decreasing sequence of measurable sets A = A_1\supset A_2 \supset A_3 \supset \cdots such that \mu(A) = \mu(A_1) > \mu(A_2) > \mu(A_3) > \cdots > 0. This may not be true for measures having atoms; see the first example above. It turns out that non-atomic measures actually have a continuum of values. It can be proved that if \mu is a non-atomic measure and A is a measurable set with \mu(A) > 0, then for any real number b satisfying \mu(A) \geq b \geq 0 there exists a measurable subset B of A such that \mu(B) = b. This theorem is due to
Wacław Sierpiński Wacław Franciszek Sierpiński (; 14 March 1882 – 21 October 1969) was a Polish mathematician. He was known for contributions to set theory (research on the axiom of choice and the continuum hypothesis), number theory, theory of functions, and to ...
. It is reminiscent of the
intermediate value theorem In mathematical analysis, the intermediate value theorem states that if f is a continuous function whose domain contains the interval , then it takes on any given value between f(a) and f(b) at some point within the interval. This has two impor ...
for continuous functions. Sketch of proof of Sierpiński's theorem on non-atomic measures. A slightly stronger statement, which however makes the proof easier, is that if (X, \Sigma, \mu) is a non-atomic measure space and \mu(X) = c, there exists a function S : , c\to \Sigma that is monotone with respect to inclusion, and a right-inverse to \mu : \Sigma \to , c That is, there exists a one-parameter family of measurable sets S(t) such that for all 0 \leq t \leq t' \leq c S(t) \subseteq S(t'), \mu\left (S(t)\right)=t. The proof easily follows from Zorn's lemma applied to the set of all monotone partial sections to \mu : \Gamma: = \, ordered by inclusion of graphs, \mathrm(S) \subseteq \mathrm(S'). It's then standard to show that every chain in \Gamma has an upper bound in \Gamma, and that any maximal element of \Gamma has domain , c proving the claim.


See also

*
Atom (order theory) In the mathematical field of order theory, an element ''a'' of a partially ordered set with least element 0 is an atom if 0 < ''a'' and there is no ''x'' such that 0 < ''x'' < ''a''. Equivalently, one may define an atom to be an element that is ...
— an analogous concept in order theory *
Dirac delta function In mathematics, the Dirac delta distribution ( distribution), also known as the unit impulse, is a generalized function or distribution over the real numbers, whose value is zero everywhere except at zero, and whose integral over the enti ...
*
Elementary event In probability theory, an elementary event, also called an atomic event or sample point, is an event which contains only a single outcome in the sample space. Using set theory terminology, an elementary event is a singleton. Elementary events a ...
, also known as an atomic event


Notes


References

* * {{Cite book , author1=Butnariu, Dan , author2=Klement, E. P. , title=Triangular norm-based measures and games with fuzzy coalitions , year=1993 , publisher=Kluwer Academic , location=Dordrecht , isbn=0-7923-2369-6 , page=87


External links


Atom
at The Encyclopedia of Mathematics Measure theory