HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the
foundations of mathematics Foundations of mathematics is the study of the philosophical and logical and/or algorithmic basis of mathematics, or, in a broader sense, the mathematical investigation of what underlies the philosophical theories concerning the nature of mathe ...
, von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG) is an
axiomatic set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
that is a conservative extension of Zermelo–Fraenkel–choice set theory (ZFC). NBG introduces the notion of
class Class or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used differently ...
, which is a collection of sets defined by a
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
whose quantifiers range only over sets. NBG can define classes that are larger than sets, such as the class of all sets and the class of all ordinals.
Morse–Kelley set theory In the foundations of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), Kelley–Morse set theory (KM), Morse–Tarski set theory (MT), Quine–Morse set theory (QM) or the system of Quine and Morse is a first-order axiomatic set theory that is closely ...
(MK) allows classes to be defined by formulas whose quantifiers range over classes. NBG is finitely axiomatizable, while ZFC and MK are not. A key theorem of NBG is the class existence theorem, which states that for every formula whose quantifiers range only over sets, there is a class consisting of the sets satisfying the formula. This class is built by mirroring the step-by-step construction of the formula with classes. Since all set-theoretic formulas are constructed from two kinds of atomic formulas ( membership and equality) and finitely many logical symbols, only finitely many
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s are needed to build the classes satisfying them. This is why NBG is finitely axiomatizable. Classes are also used for other constructions, for handling the set-theoretic paradoxes, and for stating the axiom of global choice, which is stronger than ZFC's
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
.
John von Neumann John von Neumann (; hu, Neumann János Lajos, ; December 28, 1903 – February 8, 1957) was a Hungarian-American mathematician, physicist, computer scientist, engineer and polymath. He was regarded as having perhaps the widest c ...
introduced classes into set theory in 1925. The primitive notions of his theory were function and
argument An argument is a statement or group of statements called premises intended to determine the degree of truth or acceptability of another statement called conclusion. Arguments can be studied from three main perspectives: the logical, the dialecti ...
. Using these notions, he defined class and set.; English translation: .
Paul Bernays Paul Isaac Bernays (17 October 1888 – 18 September 1977) was a Swiss mathematician who made significant contributions to mathematical logic, axiomatic set theory, and the philosophy of mathematics. He was an assistant and close collaborator of ...
reformulated von Neumann's theory by taking class and set as primitive notions., pp. 66–67.
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imm ...
simplified Bernays' theory for his
relative consistency In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent i ...
proof of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
and the generalized continuum hypothesis..


Classes in set theory


The uses of classes

Classes have several uses in NBG: * They produce a finite axiomatization of set theory. * They are used to state a "very strong form of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
".—namely, the axiom of global choice: There exists a global choice function G defined on the class of all nonempty sets such that G(x) \in x for every nonempty set x. This is stronger than ZFC's axiom of choice: For every set s of nonempty sets, there exists a
choice function A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on some collection ''X'' of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set ''S'' in that collection to ''S'' by ''f''(''S''); ''f''(''S'') maps ''S'' to ...
f defined on s such that f(x) \in x for all x \in s. * The set-theoretic paradoxes are handled by recognizing that some classes cannot be sets. For example, assume that the class Ord of all ordinals is a set. Then Ord is a transitive set
well-order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set ''S'' is a total order on ''S'' with the property that every non-empty subset of ''S'' has a least element in this ordering. The set ''S'' together with the well-or ...
ed by \in. So, by definition, Ord is an ordinal. Hence, Ord \in Ord, which contradicts \in being a well-ordering of Ord. Therefore, Ord is not a set. Because a class that is not a set is called a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
, Ord is a proper class. * Proper classes are useful in constructions. In his proof of the relative consistency of the axiom of global choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis, Gödel used proper classes to build the constructible universe. He constructed a function on the class of all ordinals that, for each ordinal, builds a constructible set by applying a set-building operation to previously constructed sets. The constructible universe is the
image An image is a visual representation of something. It can be two-dimensional, three-dimensional, or somehow otherwise feed into the visual system to convey information. An image can be an artifact, such as a photograph or other two-dimensio ...
of this function.


Axiom schema versus class existence theorem

Once classes are added to the language of ZFC, it is easy to transform ZFC into a set theory with classes. First, the axiom schema of class comprehension is added. This axiom schema states: For every formula \phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n) that quantifies only over sets, there exists a class A consisting of the satisfying the formula—that is, \forall x_1 \cdots \,\forall x_n x_1, \ldots , x_n) \in A \iff \phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n) Then the axiom schema of replacement is replaced by a single axiom that uses a class. Finally, ZFC's axiom of extensionality is modified to handle classes: If two classes have the same elements, then they are identical. The other axioms of ZFC are not modified. This theory is not finitely axiomatized. ZFC's replacement schema has been replaced by a single axiom, but the axiom schema of class comprehension has been introduced. To produce a theory with finitely many axioms, the axiom schema of class comprehension is first replaced with finitely many class existence axioms. Then these axioms are used to prove the class existence theorem, which implies every instance of the axiom schema. The proof of this theorem requires only seven class existence axioms, which are used to convert the construction of a formula into the construction of a class satisfying the formula.


Axiomatization of NBG


Classes and sets

NBG has two types of objects: classes and sets. Intuitively, every set is also a class. There are two ways to axiomatize this. Bernays used
many-sorted logic Many-sorted logic can reflect formally our intention not to handle the universe as a homogeneous collection of objects, but to partition it in a way that is similar to types in typeful programming. Both functional and assertive "parts of speech" ...
with two sorts: classes and sets. Gödel avoided sorts by introducing primitive predicates: \mathfrak(A) for "A is a class" and \mathfrak(A) for "A is a set" (in German, "set" is ''Menge''). He also introduced axioms stating that every set is a class and that if class A is a member of a class, then A is a set.. Using predicates is the standard way to eliminate sorts.
Elliott Mendelson Elliott Mendelson (May 24, 1931 – May 7, 2020) was an American logician. He was a professor of mathematics at Queens College of the City University of New York, and the Graduate Center, CUNY. He was Jr. Fellow, Society of Fellows, Harvard Un ...
modified Gödel's approach by having everything be a class and defining the set predicate M(A) as \exists C(A \in C). This modification eliminates Gödel's class predicate and his two axioms. Bernays' two-sorted approach may appear more natural at first, but it creates a more complex theory. In Bernays' theory, every set has two representations: one as a set and the other as a class. Also, there are two membership relations: the first, denoted by "∈", is between two sets; the second, denoted by "η", is between a set and a class. This redundancy is required by many-sorted logic because variables of different sorts range over disjoint subdomains of the
domain of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse, also called the universe of discourse, universal set, or simply universe, is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. Overview The doma ...
. The differences between these two approaches do not affect what can be proved, but they do affect how statements are written. In Gödel's approach, A \in C where A and C are classes is a valid statement. In Bernays' approach this statement has no meaning. However, if A is a set, there is an equivalent statement: Define "set a represents class A" if they have the same sets as members—that is, \forall x(x \in a \iff x \;\eta \;A). The statement a \;\eta \;C where set a represents class A is equivalent to Gödel's A \in C. The approach adopted in this article is that of Gödel with Mendelson's modification. This means that NBG is an axiomatic system in first-order predicate logic with equality, and its only primitive notions are class and the membership relation.


Definitions and axioms of extensionality and pairing

A set is a class that belongs to at least one class: A is a set if and only if \exist C(A \in C). A class that is not a set is called a proper class: A is a proper class if and only if \forall C(A \notin C). Therefore, every class is either a set or a proper class, and no class is both. Gödel introduced the convention that uppercase variables range over classes, while lowercase variables range over sets. Gödel also used names that begin with an uppercase letter to denote particular classes, including functions and relations defined on the class of all sets. Gödel's convention is used in this article. It allows us to write: * \exist x\, \phi(x) instead of \exist x \bigl(\exist C (x \in C) \land \phi(x)\bigr) * \forall x\, \phi(x) instead of \forall x \bigl(\exist C (x \in C) \implies \phi(x)\bigr) The following axioms and definitions are needed for the proof of the class existence theorem. Axiom of extensionality. If two classes have the same elements, then they are identical. :\forall A \,\forall B \, forall x(x \in A \iff x \in B) \implies A = B/math> This axiom generalizes ZFC's axiom of extensionality to classes.
Axiom of pairing In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It was introduced by as a special case of his axiom of elementary set ...
. If x and y are sets, then there exists a set p whose only members are x and y. :\forall x \,\forall y \,\exists p \,\forall z \, \in p \iff (z = x \,\lor\, z = y)/math> As in ZFC, the axiom of extensionality implies the uniqueness of the set p, which allows us to introduce the notation \.
Ordered pair In mathematics, an ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is a pair of objects. The order in which the objects appear in the pair is significant: the ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a'') unless ''a'' = ''b''. (In con ...
s are defined by: :(x, y) = \ Tuples are defined inductively using ordered pairs: :(x_1) = x_1, :\text n > 1\!: (x_1, \ldots, x_, x_n) = ((x_1, \ldots, x_), x_n).


Class existence axioms and axiom of regularity

Class existence axioms will be used to prove the class existence theorem: For every formula in n free set variables that quantifies only over sets, there exists a class of that satisfy it. The following example starts with two classes that are functions and builds a
composite function In mathematics, function composition is an operation that takes two functions and , and produces a function such that . In this operation, the function is applied to the result of applying the function to . That is, the functions and ...
. This example illustrates the techniques that are needed to prove the class existence theorem, which lead to the class existence axioms that are needed. : The class existence axioms are divided into two groups: axioms handling language primitives and axioms handling tuples. There are four axioms in the first group and three axioms in the second group. Axioms for handling language primitives: Membership. There exists a class E containing all the ordered pairs whose first component is a member of the second component. :\exists E \,\forall x \,\forall y \, x,y) \in E \iff x \in y! Intersection (conjunction). For any two classes A and B, there is a class C consisting precisely of the sets that belong to both A and B. :\forall A \,\forall B \,\exists C \,\forall x \, \in C \iff (x \in A \,\land\, x \in B)/math> Complement (negation). For any class A, there is a class B consisting precisely of the sets not belonging to A. :\forall A \,\exists B \,\forall x \, \in B \iff \neg(x \in A)/math> Domain (existential quantifier). For any class A, there is a class B consisting precisely of the first components of the ordered pairs of A. :\forall A \,\exists B \,\forall x \, \in B \iff \exists y((x,y) \in A)/math> By the axiom of extensionality, class C in the intersection axiom and class B in the complement and domain axioms are unique. They will be denoted by: A \cap B, \complement A, and Dom(A), respectively. On the other hand, extensionality is not applicable to E in the membership axiom since it specifies only those sets in E that are ordered pairs. The first three axioms imply the existence of the empty class and the class of all sets: The membership axiom implies the existence of a class E. The intersection and complement axioms imply the existence of E \cap \complement E, which is empty. By the axiom of extensionality, this class is unique; it is denoted by \empty. The complement of \empty is the class V of all sets, which is also unique by extensionality. The set predicate M(A), which was defined as \exists C(A \in C), is now redefined as A \in V to avoid quantifying over classes. Axioms for handling tuples: Product by V. For any class A, there is a class B consisting of the ordered pairs whose first component belongs to A. :\forall A \,\exists B \,\forall u \, \in B \iff \exists x \, \exists y \,(u = (x, y) \land x \in A)/math> Circular permutation. For any class A, there is a class B whose 3tuples are obtained by applying the circular permutation (y,z,x) \mapsto (x,y,z) to the 3tuples of A. :\forall A \,\exists B \,\forall x \,\forall y \,\forall z \, x,y,z) \in B \iff (y,z,x) \in A/math> Transposition. For any class A, there is a class B whose 3tuples are obtained by transposing the last two components of the 3tuples of A. :\forall A \,\exists B \,\forall x \,\forall y \,\forall z \, x,y,z) \in B \iff (x,z,y) \in A/math> By extensionality, the product by V axiom implies the existence of a unique class, which is denoted by A \times V. This axiom is used to define the class V^n of all : V^1 = V and V^ = V^n \times V.\, If A is a class, extensionality implies that A \cap V^n is the unique class consisting of the of A. For example, the membership axiom produces a class E that may contain elements that are not ordered pairs, while the intersection E \cap V^2 contains only the ordered pairs of E. The circular permutation and transposition axioms do not imply the existence of unique classes because they specify only the 3tuples of class B. By specifying the 3tuples, these axioms also specify the for n \ge 4 since: (x_1, \ldots, x_, x_, x_n) = ((x_1, \ldots, x_), x_, x_n). The axioms for handling tuples and the domain axiom imply the following lemma, which is used in the proof of the class existence theorem. One more axiom is needed to prove the class existence theorem: the
axiom of regularity In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every non-empty set ''A'' contains an element that is disjoint from ''A''. In first-order logic, the a ...
. Since the existence of the empty class has been proved, the usual statement of this axiom is given.
Axiom of regularity In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every non-empty set ''A'' contains an element that is disjoint from ''A''. In first-order logic, the a ...
. Every nonempty set has at least one element with which it has no element in common. \forall a\, \neq \empty \implies \exists u(u \in a \land u \cap a = \empty) This axiom implies that a set cannot belong to itself: Assume that x \in x and let a = \. Then x \cap a \ne \empty since x \in x \cap a. This contradicts the axiom of regularity because x is the only element in a. Therefore, x \notin x. The axiom of regularity also prohibits infinite descending membership sequences of sets: \cdots \in x_ \in x_n \in \cdots \in x_1 \in x_0. Gödel stated regularity for classes rather than for sets in his 1940 monograph, which was based on lectures given in 1938. In 1939, he proved that regularity for sets implies regularity for classes.


Class existence theorem

The theorem's proof will be done in two steps: # Transformation rules are used to transform the given formula \phi into an equivalent formula that simplifies the inductive part of the proof. For example, the only logical symbols in the transformed formula are \neg, \land, and \exists, so the induction handles logical symbols with just three cases. # The class existence theorem is proved inductively for transformed formulas. Guided by the structure of the transformed formula, the class existence axioms are used to produce the unique class of satisfying the formula. Transformation rules. In rules 1 and 2 below, \Delta and \Gamma denote set or class variables. These two rules eliminate all occurrences of class variables before an \in and all occurrences of equality. Each time rule 1 or 2 is applied to a subformula, i is chosen so that z_i differs from the other variables in the current formula. The three rules are repeated until there are no subformulas to which they can be applied. This produces a formula that is built only with \neg, \land, \exists, \in, set variables, and class variables Y_k where Y_k does not appear before an \in. # \,Y_k \in \Gamma is transformed into \exists z_i(z_i = Y_k \,\land\, z_i \in \Gamma). # Extensionality is used to transform \Delta = \Gamma into \forall z_i(z_i \in \Delta \iff z_i \in \Gamma). # Logical identities are used to transform subformulas containing \lor, \implies, \iff, and \forall to subformulas that only use \neg, \land, and \exists. Transformation rules:
bound variables In mathematics, and in other disciplines involving formal languages, including mathematical logic and computer science, a free variable is a notation (symbol) that specifies places in an expression where substitution may take place and is not ...
. Consider the composite function formula of example 1 with its free set variables replaced by x_1 and x_2: \exists t x_1, t) \in F \,\land\, (t, x_2) \in G The inductive proof will remove \exists t, which produces the formula (x_1, t) \in F \land (t, x_2) \in G. However, since the class existence theorem is stated for subscripted variables, this formula does not have the form expected by the induction hypothesis. This problem is solved by replacing the variable t with x_3. Bound variables within nested quantifiers are handled by increasing the subscript by one for each successive quantifier. This leads to rule 4, which must be applied after the other rules since rules 1 and 2 produce quantified variables. #
  • If a formula contains no free set variables other than x_1, \dots, x_n, then bound variables that are nested within q quantifiers are replaced with These variables have ''(quantifier) nesting depth'' q.
  • : Proof of the class existence theorem. The proof starts by applying the transformation rules to the given formula to produce a transformed formula. Since this formula is equivalent to the given formula, the proof is completed by proving the class existence theorem for transformed formulas. Gödel pointed out that the class existence theorem "is a metatheorem, that is, a theorem about the system BG not in the system …" It is a theorem about NBG because it is proved in the metatheory by induction on NBG formulas. Also, its proof—instead of invoking finitely many NBG axioms—inductively describes how to use NBG axioms to construct a class satisfying a given formula. For every formula, this description can be turned into a constructive existence proof that is in NBG. Therefore, this metatheorem can generate the NBG proofs that replace uses of NBG's class existence theorem. A recursive
    computer program A computer program is a sequence or set of instructions in a programming language for a computer to Execution (computing), execute. Computer programs are one component of software, which also includes software documentation, documentation and oth ...
    succinctly captures the construction of a class from a given formula. The definition of this program does not depend on the proof of the class existence theorem. However, the proof is needed to prove that the class constructed by the program satisfies the given formula and is built using the axioms. This program is written in
    pseudocode In computer science, pseudocode is a plain language description of the steps in an algorithm or another system. Pseudocode often uses structural conventions of a normal programming language, but is intended for human reading rather than machine re ...
    that uses a
    Pascal Pascal, Pascal's or PASCAL may refer to: People and fictional characters * Pascal (given name), including a list of people with the name * Pascal (surname), including a list of people and fictional characters with the name ** Blaise Pascal, Frenc ...
    -style case statement. \begin \mathbf \;\text(\phi, \,n) \\ \quad\begin \mathbf\!: \;\,&\phi \text \phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n, Y_1, \ldots, Y_m); \\ &n \text n\text \\ \;\;\;\;\mathbf\!: \;\,&\text A \text n\text \\ &\,\forall x_1 \cdots \,\forall x_n x_1, \ldots , x_n) \in A \iff \phi(x_1, \ldots, x_n, Y_1, \ldots, Y_m) \end \\ \mathbf \\ \quad \mathbf \;\phi \;\mathbf \\ \qquad \begin x_i \in x_j: \;\;&\mathbf \;\,E_; &&\text E_ \;\,= \ \\ x_i \in Y_k: \;\;&\mathbf \;\,E_; &&\text E_ = \ \\ \neg\psi: \;\;&\mathbf \;\,\complement_\text(\psi, \,n); &&\text \complement_\text(\psi, \,n) = V^n \setminus \text(\psi, \,n) \\ \psi_1 \land \psi_2: \;\;&\mathbf \;\,\text(\psi_1, \,n) \cap \text(\psi_2, \,n);&& \\ \;\;\;\;\,\exists x_(\psi): \;\;&\mathbf \;\,Dom(\text(\psi, \,n+1)); &&\text x_ \text \psi; \text(\psi, \,n+1) \\ &\ &&\text (n+1)\text \end \\ \quad \mathbf \\ \mathbf \end Let \phi be the formula of example 2. The function call A = Class(\phi, 1) generates the class A, which is compared below with \phi. This shows that the construction of the class A mirrors the construction of its defining formula \phi. \begin &\phi \;&&= \;\;\exists x_2\,(x_2 \!\in\! x_1 \land \;\;\neg\;\;\;\;\exists x_3\;(x_3 \!\in\! x_2)) \,\land \;\;\,\exists x_2\,(x_2 \!\in\! x_1 \land \;\;\,\exists x_3\,(x_3 \!\in\! x_2 \,\land\;\;\neg\;\;\;\;\exists x_4\;(x_4 \!\in\! x_3))) \\ &A \;&&= Dom\,(\;E_\; \cap \;\complement_\,Dom\,(\;E_\;)) \,\cap\, Dom\,(\;E_\;\cap \, Dom\,(\;\,E_\; \cap \;\complement_\,Dom\,(\;E_\;))) \end


    Extending the class existence theorem

    Gödel extended the class existence theorem to formulas \phi containing relations over classes (such as Y_1 \subseteq Y_2 and the
    unary relation In mathematics, a finitary relation over sets is a subset of the Cartesian product ; that is, it is a set of ''n''-tuples consisting of elements ''x'i'' in ''X'i''. Typically, the relation describes a possible connection between the eleme ...
    M(Y_1)), special classes (such as Ord), and
    operation Operation or Operations may refer to: Arts, entertainment and media * ''Operation'' (game), a battery-operated board game that challenges dexterity * Operation (music), a term used in musical set theory * ''Operations'' (magazine), Multi-Man ...
    s (such as (x_1, x_2) and x_1 \cap Y_1). To extend the class existence theorem, the formulas defining relations, special classes, and operations must quantify only over sets. Then \phi can be transformed into an equivalent formula satisfying the hypothesis of the class existence theorem. The following definitions specify how formulas define relations, special classes, and operations: # A relation R is defined by: R(Z_1, \dots, Z_k) \iff \psi_R(Z_1, \dots, Z_k). # A special class C is defined by: u \in C \iff \psi_C(u). # An operation P is defined by: u \in P(Z_1, \dots, Z_k) \iff \psi_P(u, Z_1, \dots, Z_k). A is defined by: # Variables and special classes are terms. # If P is an operation with k arguments and \Gamma_1, \dots, \Gamma_k are terms, then P(\Gamma_1, \dots, \Gamma_k) is a term. The following transformation rules eliminate relations, special classes, and operations. Each time rule 2b, 3b, or 4 is applied to a subformula, i is chosen so that z_i differs from the other variables in the current formula. The rules are repeated until there are no subformulas to which they can be applied. \, \Gamma_1, \dots, \Gamma_k, \Gamma, and \Delta denote terms. # A relation R(Z_1, \dots, Z_k) is replaced by its defining formula \psi_R(Z_1, \dots, Z_k). # Let \psi_C(u) be the defining formula for the special class C. # Let \psi_P(u, Z_1, \dots, Z_k) be the defining formula for the operation P(Z_1, \dots, Z_k). # Extensionality is used to transform \Delta = \Gamma into \forall z_i(z_i \in \Delta \iff z_i \in \Gamma). : :


    Set axioms

    The axioms of pairing and regularity, which were needed for the proof of the class existence theorem, have been given above. NBG contains four other set axioms. Three of these axioms deal with class operations being applied to sets. Definition. F is a function if F \subseteq V^2 \land \forall x\, \forall y\, \forall z\, x,y) \in F \,\land\, (x,z) \in F \implies y = z In set theory, the definition of a function does not require specifying the domain or codomain of the function (see Function (set theory)). NBG's definition of function generalizes ZFC's definition from a set of ordered pairs to a class of ordered pairs. ZFC's definitions of the set operations of
    image An image is a visual representation of something. It can be two-dimensional, three-dimensional, or somehow otherwise feed into the visual system to convey information. An image can be an artifact, such as a photograph or other two-dimensio ...
    , union, and
    power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
    are also generalized to class operations. The image of class A under the function F is F = \. This definition does not require that A \subseteq Dom(F). The union of class A is \cup A = \. The power class of A is \mathcal(A) = \. The extended version of the class existence theorem implies the existence of these classes. The axioms of replacement, union, and
    power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
    imply that when these operations are applied to sets, they produce sets. Axiom of replacement. If F is a function and a is a set, then F /math>, the
    image An image is a visual representation of something. It can be two-dimensional, three-dimensional, or somehow otherwise feed into the visual system to convey information. An image can be an artifact, such as a photograph or other two-dimensio ...
    of a under F, is a set. \forall F \,\forall a \, \text\implies \exists b \,\forall y\,(y \in b \iff \exists x(x \in a \,\land\, (x, y) \in F)) Not having the requirement A \subseteq Dom(F) in the definition of F /math> produces a stronger axiom of replacement, which is used in the following proof. Axiom of union. If a is a set, then there is a set containing \cup a. \forall a\, \exists b\, \forall x\, ,\exists y(x \in y\, \,\land\, y \in a) \implies x \in b\, Axiom of power set. If a is a set, then there is a set containing \mathcal(a). :\forall a\, \exists b\, \forall x\, (x \subseteq a \implies x \in b). Axiom of infinity. There exists a nonempty set a such that for all x in a, there exists a y in a such that x is a proper subset of y. \exists a\, exists u(u \in a) \,\land\, \forall x(x \in a \implies \exists y(y \in a \,\land\, x \subset y)) The axioms of infinity and replacement prove the existence of the
    empty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in othe ...
    . In the discussion of the class existence axioms, the existence of the empty class \empty was proved. We now prove that \empty is a set. Let function F = \empty and let a be the set given by the axiom of infinity. By replacement, the image of a under F, which equals \empty, is a set. NBG's axiom of infinity is implied by ZFC's
    axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing th ...
    : \,\exists a\, empty \in a \,\land\, \forall x(x \in a \implies x \cup \ \in a)\, The first conjunct of ZFC's axiom, \empty \in a, implies the first conjunct of NBG's axiom. The second conjunct of ZFC's axiom, \forall x(x \in a \implies x \cup \ \in a), implies the second conjunct of NBG's axiom since x \subset x \cup \. To prove ZFC's axiom of infinity from NBG's axiom of infinity requires some of the other NBG axioms (see Weak axiom of infinity).


    Axiom of global choice

    The class concept allows NBG to have a stronger axiom of choice than ZFC. A
    choice function A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on some collection ''X'' of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set ''S'' in that collection to ''S'' by ''f''(''S''); ''f''(''S'') maps ''S'' to ...
    is a function f defined on a set s of nonempty sets such that f(x) \in x for all x \in s. ZFC's axiom of choice states that there exists a choice function for every set of nonempty sets. A global choice function is a function G defined on the class of all nonempty sets such that G(x) \in x for every nonempty set x. The axiom of global choice states that there exists a global choice function. This axiom implies ZFC's axiom of choice since for every set s of nonempty sets, G\vert_s (the restriction of G to s) is a choice function for s. In 1964, William B. Easton proved that global choice is stronger than the axiom of choice by using forcing to construct a model that satisfies the axiom of choice and all the axioms of NBG except the axiom of global choice. The axiom of global choice is equivalent to every class having a well-ordering, while ZFC's axiom of choice is equivalent to every set having a well-ordering. Axiom of global choice. There exists a function that chooses an element from every nonempty set. :\exists G\, \text\, \land \forall x(x \ne \empty \implies \exists y(y \in x \land (x,y) \in G))


    History


    Von Neumann's 1925 axiom system

    Von Neumann published an introductory article on his axiom system in 1925. In 1928, he provided a detailed treatment of his system. Von Neumann based his axiom system on two domains of primitive objects: functions and arguments. These domains overlap—objects that are in both domains are called argument-functions. Functions correspond to classes in NBG, and argument-functions correspond to sets. Von Neumann's primitive operation is
    function application In mathematics, function application is the act of applying a function to an argument from its domain so as to obtain the corresponding value from its range. In this sense, function application can be thought of as the opposite of function abst ...
    , denoted by 'a'', ''x''rather than ''a''(''x'') where ''a'' is a function and ''x'' is an argument. This operation produces an argument. Von Neumann defined classes and sets using functions and argument-functions that take only two values, ''A'' and ''B''. He defined ''x'' ∈ ''a'' if 'a'', ''x''nbsp;≠ ''A''. Von Neumann's work in set theory was influenced by
    Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( , ;  – January 6, 1918) was a German mathematician. He played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor established the importance o ...
    's articles, Ernst Zermelo's 1908 axioms for set theory, and the 1922 critiques of Zermelo's set theory that were given independently by Abraham Fraenkel and Thoralf Skolem. Both Fraenkel and Skolem pointed out that Zermelo's axioms cannot prove the existence of the set where ''Z''0 is the set of
    natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
    s and ''Z''''n''+1 is the
    power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
    of ''Z''''n''. They then introduced the axiom of replacement, which would guarantee the existence of such sets. However, they were reluctant to adopt this axiom: Fraenkel stated "that Replacement was too strong an axiom for 'general set theory'", while "Skolem only wrote that 'we could introduce' Replacement". Von Neumann worked on the problems of Zermelo set theory and provided solutions for some of them: * A theory of ordinals ** Problem: Cantor's theory of
    ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
    s cannot be developed in Zermelo set theory because it lacks the axiom of replacement. ** Solution: Von Neumann recovered Cantor's theory by defining the ordinals using sets that are well-ordered by the ∈-relation, and by using the axiom of replacement to prove key theorems about the ordinals, such as every well-ordered set is order-isomorphic with an ordinal. In contrast to Fraenkel and Skolem, von Neumann emphasized how important the replacement axiom is for set theory: "In fact, I believe that no theory of ordinals is possible at all without this axiom." * A criterion identifying classes that are too large to be sets ** Problem: Zermelo did not provide such a criterion. His set theory avoids the large classes that lead to the paradoxes, but it leaves out many sets, such as the one mentioned by Fraenkel and Skolem. ** Solution: Von Neumann introduced the criterion: A class is too large to be a set if and only if it can be mapped onto the class ''V'' of all sets. Von Neumann realized that the set-theoretic paradoxes could be avoided by not allowing such large classes to be members of any class. Combining this restriction with his criterion, he obtained his axiom of limitation of size: A class ''C'' is not a member of any class if and only if ''C'' can be mapped onto ''V''. * Finite axiomatization ** Problem: Zermelo had used the imprecise concept of "definite propositional function" in his axiom of separation. ** Solutions: Skolem introduced the axiom schema of separation that was later used in ZFC, and Fraenkel introduced an equivalent solution. However, Zermelo rejected both approaches "particularly because they implicitly involve the concept of natural number which, in Zermelo's view, should be based upon set theory." Von Neumann avoided axiom schemas by formalizing the concept of "definite propositional function" with his functions, whose construction requires only finitely many axioms. This led to his set theory having finitely many axioms. In 1961,
    Richard Montague Richard Merritt Montague (September 20, 1930 – March 7, 1971) was an American mathematician and philosopher who made contributions to mathematical logic and the philosophy of language. He is known for proposing Montague grammar to formaliz ...
    proved that ZFC cannot be finitely axiomatized. * The axiom of regularity ** Problem: Zermelo set theory starts with the empty set and an infinite set, and iterates the axioms of pairing, union, power set, separation, and choice to generate new sets. However, it does not restrict sets to these. For example, it allows sets that are not well-founded, such as a set ''x'' satisfying ''x'' ∈ ''x''. ** Solutions: Fraenkel introduced an axiom to exclude these sets. Von Neumann analyzed Fraenkel's axiom and stated that it was not "precisely formulated", but it would approximately say: "Besides the sets ... whose existence is absolutely required by the axioms, there are no further sets." Von Neumann proposed the axiom of regularity as a way to exclude non-well-founded sets, but did not include it in his axiom system. In 1930, Zermelo became the first to publish an axiom system that included regularity.


    Von Neumann's 1929 axiom system

    In 1929, von Neumann published an article containing the axioms that would lead to NBG. This article was motivated by his concern about the consistency of the axiom of limitation of size. He stated that this axiom "does a lot, actually too much." Besides implying the axioms of separation and replacement, and the well-ordering theorem, it also implies that any class whose
    cardinality In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
    is less than that of ''V'' is a set. Von Neumann thought that this last implication went beyond Cantorian set theory and concluded: "We must therefore discuss whether its he axiom'sconsistency is not even more problematic than an axiomatization of set theory that does not go beyond the necessary Cantorian framework." Von Neumann started his consistency investigation by introducing his 1929 axiom system, which contains all the axioms of his 1925 axiom system except the axiom of limitation of size. He replaced this axiom with two of its consequences, the axiom of replacement and a choice axiom. Von Neumann's choice axiom states: "Every relation ''R'' has a subclass that is a function with the same domain as ''R''." Let ''S'' be von Neumann's 1929 axiom system. Von Neumann introduced the axiom system ''S'' + Regularity (which consists of ''S'' and the axiom of regularity) to demonstrate that his 1925 system is consistent relative to ''S''. He proved: # If ''S'' is consistent, then ''S'' + Regularity is consistent. # ''S'' + Regularity implies the axiom of limitation of size. Since this is the only axiom of his 1925 axiom system that ''S'' + Regularity does not have, ''S'' + Regularity implies all the axioms of his 1925 system. These results imply: If ''S'' is consistent, then von Neumann's 1925 axiom system is consistent. Proof: If ''S'' is consistent, then ''S'' + Regularity is consistent (result 1). Using
    proof by contradiction In logic and mathematics, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition, by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction. Proof by contradiction is also known ...
    , assume that the 1925 axiom system is inconsistent, or equivalently: the 1925 axiom system implies a contradiction. Since ''S'' + Regularity implies the axioms of the 1925 system (result 2), ''S'' + Regularity also implies a contradiction. However, this contradicts the consistency of ''S'' + Regularity. Therefore, if ''S'' is consistent, then von Neumann's 1925 axiom system is consistent. Since ''S'' is his 1929 axiom system, von Neumann's 1925 axiom system is consistent relative to his 1929 axiom system, which is closer to Cantorian set theory. The major differences between Cantorian set theory and the 1929 axiom system are classes and von Neumann's choice axiom. The axiom system ''S'' + Regularity was modified by Bernays and Gödel to produce the equivalent NBG axiom system.


    Bernays' axiom system

    In 1929,
    Paul Bernays Paul Isaac Bernays (17 October 1888 – 18 September 1977) was a Swiss mathematician who made significant contributions to mathematical logic, axiomatic set theory, and the philosophy of mathematics. He was an assistant and close collaborator of ...
    started modifying von Neumann's new axiom system by taking classes and sets as primitives. He published his work in a series of articles appearing from 1937 to 1954. Bernays stated that: Bernays handled sets and classes in a two-sorted logic and introduced two membership primitives: one for membership in sets and one for membership in classes. With these primitives, he rewrote and simplified von Neumann's 1929 axioms. Bernays also included the axiom of regularity in his axiom system.


    Gödel's axiom system (NBG)

    In 1931, Bernays sent a letter containing his set theory to
    Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( , ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel had an imm ...
    . Gödel simplified Bernays' theory by making every set a class, which allowed him to use just one sort and one membership primitive. He also weakened some of Bernays' axioms and replaced von Neumann's choice axiom with the equivalent axiom of global choice. Gödel used his axioms in his 1940 monograph on the relative consistency of global choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis. Several reasons have been given for Gödel choosing NBG for his monograph: * Gödel gave a mathematical reason—NBG's global choice produces a stronger consistency theorem: "This stronger form of the axiom f choice if consistent with the other axioms, implies, of course, that a weaker form is also consistent." * Robert Solovay conjectured: "My guess is that he ödelwished to avoid a discussion of the technicalities involved in developing the rudiments of
    model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (math ...
    within axiomatic set theory." * Kenneth Kunen gave a reason for Gödel avoiding this discussion: "There is also a much more combinatorial approach to L constructible_universe.html" ;"title="he constructible universe">he constructible universe developed by ... ödel in his 1940 monographin an attempt to explain his work to non-logicians. ... This approach has the merit of removing all vestiges of logic from the treatment of L." * Charles Parsons provided a philosophical reason for Gödel's choice: "This view hat 'property of set' is a primitive of set theorymay be reflected in Gödel's choice of a theory with class variables as the framework for ... is monograph" Gödel's achievement together with the details of his presentation led to the prominence that NBG would enjoy for the next two decades. In 1963, Paul Cohen proved his
    independence Independence is a condition of a person, nation, country, or state in which residents and population, or some portion thereof, exercise self-government, and usually sovereignty, over its territory. The opposite of independence is the stat ...
    proofs for ZF with the help of some tools that Gödel had developed for his relative consistency proofs for NBG. Later, ZFC became more popular than NBG. This was caused by several factors, including the extra work required to handle forcing in NBG, Cohen's 1966 presentation of forcing, which used ZF, and the proof that NBG is a conservative extension of ZFC.


    NBG, ZFC, and MK

    NBG is not logically equivalent to ZFC because its language is more expressive: it can make statements about classes, which cannot be made in ZFC. However, NBG and ZFC imply the same statements about sets. Therefore, NBG is a conservative extension of ZFC. NBG implies theorems that ZFC does not imply, but since NBG is a conservative extension, these theorems must involve proper classes. For example, it is a theorem of NBG that the global axiom of choice implies that the proper class ''V'' can be well-ordered and that every proper class can be put into one-to-one correspondence with ''V''. One consequence of conservative extension is that ZFC and NBG are equiconsistent. Proving this uses the
    principle of explosion In classical logic, intuitionistic logic and similar logical systems, the principle of explosion (, 'from falsehood, anything ollows; or ), or the principle of Pseudo-Scotus, is the law according to which any statement can be proven from a ...
    : from a contradiction, everything is provable. Assume that either ZFC or NBG is inconsistent. Then the inconsistent theory implies the contradictory statements ∅ = ∅ and ∅ ≠ ∅, which are statements about sets. By the conservative extension property, the other theory also implies these statements. Therefore, it is also inconsistent. So although NBG is more expressive, it is equiconsistent with ZFC. This result together with von Neumann's 1929 relative consistency proof implies that his 1925 axiom system with the axiom of limitation of size is equiconsistent with ZFC. This completely resolves von Neumann's concern about the relative consistency of this powerful axiom since ZFC is within the Cantorian framework. Even though NBG is a conservative extension of ZFC, a theorem may have a shorter and more elegant proof in NBG than in ZFC (or vice versa). For a survey of known results of this nature, see .
    Morse–Kelley set theory In the foundations of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), Kelley–Morse set theory (KM), Morse–Tarski set theory (MT), Quine–Morse set theory (QM) or the system of Quine and Morse is a first-order axiomatic set theory that is closely ...
    has an axiom schema of class comprehension that includes formulas whose quantifiers range over classes. MK is a stronger theory than NBG because MK proves the consistency of NBG, while Gödel's second incompleteness theorem implies that NBG cannot prove the consistency of NBG. For a discussion of some ontological and other philosophical issues posed by NBG, especially when contrasted with ZFC and MK, see Appendix C of .


    Models

    ZFC, NBG, and MK have models describable in terms of the
    cumulative hierarchy In mathematics, specifically set theory, a cumulative hierarchy is a family of sets W_\alpha indexed by ordinals \alpha such that * W_\alpha \subseteq W_ * If \lambda is a limit ordinal, then W_\lambda = \bigcup_ W_ Some authors additionally r ...
    ''Vα'' and the constructible hierarchy ''Lα''. Let ''V'' include an inaccessible cardinal κ, let ''X'' ⊆ ''Vκ'', and let Def(''X'') denote the class of first-order definable subsets of ''X'' with parameters. In symbols where "(X,\in)" denotes the model with
    domain Domain may refer to: Mathematics *Domain of a function, the set of input values for which the (total) function is defined ** Domain of definition of a partial function ** Natural domain of a partial function **Domain of holomorphy of a function * ...
    X and relation \in, and "\models" denotes the
    satisfaction relation First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantif ...
    : \operatorname(X) := \Bigl\. Then: * (''V''κ, ∈) and (''L''κ, ∈) are models of ZFC. * (''V''κ, ''V''κ+1, ∈) is a model of MK where ''V''κ consists of the sets of the model and ''V''κ+1 consists of the classes of the model. Since a model of MK is a model of NBG, this model is also a model of NBG. * (''V''κ, Def(''V''κ), ∈) is a model of Mendelson's version of NBG, which replaces NBG's axiom of global choice with ZFC's axiom of choice. The axioms of ZFC are true in this model because (''V''κ, ∈) is a model of ZFC. In particular, ZFC's axiom of choice holds, but NBG's global choice may fail. NBG's class existence axioms are true in this model because the classes whose existence they assert can be defined by first-order definitions. For example, the membership axiom holds since the class E is defined by: E = \. * (''L''κ, ''L''κ+, ∈), where κ+ is the successor cardinal of κ, is a model of NBG. NBG's class existence axioms are true in (''L''κ, ''L''κ+, ∈). For example, the membership axiom holds since the class E is defined by: E = \. So ''E'' ∈ 𝒫(''L''κ). In his proof that GCH is true in ''L'', Gödel proved that 𝒫(''L''κ) ⊆ ''L''κ+. Therefore, ''E'' ∈ ''L''κ+, so the membership axiom is true in (''L''κ, ''L''κ+, ∈). Likewise, the other class existence axioms are true. The axiom of global choice is true because ''L''κ is well-ordered by the restriction of Gödel's function (which maps the class of ordinals to the constructible sets) to the ordinals less than κ. Therefore, (''L''κ, ''L''κ+, ∈) is a model of NBG.


    Category theory

    The ontology of NBG provides scaffolding for speaking about "large objects" without risking paradox. For instance, in some developments of
    category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, ca ...
    , a " large category" is defined as one whose
    object Object may refer to: General meanings * Object (philosophy), a thing, being, or concept ** Object (abstract), an object which does not exist at any particular time or place ** Physical object, an identifiable collection of matter * Goal, an ...
    s and
    morphism In mathematics, particularly in category theory, a morphism is a structure-preserving map from one mathematical structure to another one of the same type. The notion of morphism recurs in much of contemporary mathematics. In set theory, morphisms ...
    s make up a proper class. On the other hand, a "small category" is one whose objects and morphisms are members of a set. Thus, we can speak of the " category of all sets" or " category of all small categories" without risking paradox since NBG supports large categories. However, NBG does not support a "category of all categories" since large categories would be members of it and NBG does not allow proper classes to be members of anything. An ontological extension that enables us to talk formally about such a "category" is the
    conglomerate Conglomerate or conglomeration may refer to: * Conglomerate (company) * Conglomerate (geology) * Conglomerate (mathematics) In popular culture: * The Conglomerate (American group), a production crew and musical group founded by Busta Rhymes ** ...
    , which is a collection of classes. Then the "category of all categories" is defined by its objects: the conglomerate of all categories; and its morphisms: the conglomerate of all morphisms from ''A'' to ''B'' where ''A'' and ''B'' are objects.. On whether an ontology including classes as well as sets is adequate for category theory, see .


    Notes


    References


    Bibliography

    * . **. * . * . * . * . * . * . * . **. * . * . * . * . * . **. * . * . * . * . * . **. * . * . * . * . **. * . - Pp. 225–86 contain the classic textbook treatment of NBG, showing how it does what we expect of set theory, by grounding relations,
    order theory Order theory is a branch of mathematics that investigates the intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as "this is less than that" or "this precedes that". This article intr ...
    ,
    ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
    s,
    transfinite number In mathematics, transfinite numbers are numbers that are " infinite" in the sense that they are larger than all finite numbers, yet not necessarily absolutely infinite. These include the transfinite cardinals, which are cardinal numbers used to q ...
    s, etc. * . * . * . * . * . * . **. * . * . *. *. **English translation: . **English translation: . *. *. *.


    External links

    * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Von Neumann-Bernays-Godel set theory Foundations of mathematics John von Neumann Systems of set theory Works by Kurt Gödel