HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
computational complexity theory In theoretical computer science and mathematics, computational complexity theory focuses on classifying computational problems according to their resource usage, and relating these classes to each other. A computational problem is a task solved ...
, the time hierarchy theorems are important statements about time-bounded computation on
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer alg ...
s. Informally, these theorems say that given more time, a Turing machine can solve more problems. For example, there are problems that can be solved with ''n''2 time but not ''n'' time. The time hierarchy theorem for deterministic multi-tape Turing machines was first proven by
Richard E. Stearns Richard Edwin Stearns (born July 5, 1936) is a prominent computer scientist who, with Juris Hartmanis, received the 1993 ACM Turing Award "in recognition of their seminal paper which established the foundations for the field of computational co ...
and
Juris Hartmanis Juris Hartmanis (July 5, 1928 – July 29, 2022) was a Latvian-born American computer scientist and computational theorist who, with Richard E. Stearns, received the 1993 ACM Turing Award "in recognition of their seminal paper which establishe ...
in 1965. It was improved a year later when F. C. Hennie and Richard E. Stearns improved the efficiency of the Universal Turing machine. Consequent to the theorem, for every deterministic time-bounded
complexity class In computational complexity theory, a complexity class is a set of computational problems of related resource-based complexity. The two most commonly analyzed resources are time and memory. In general, a complexity class is defined in terms o ...
, there is a strictly larger time-bounded complexity class, and so the time-bounded hierarchy of complexity classes does not completely collapse. More precisely, the time hierarchy theorem for deterministic Turing machines states that for all time-constructible functions ''f''(''n''), :\mathsf\left(o\left(\frac\right)\right) \subsetneq \mathsf(f(n)). The time hierarchy theorem for nondeterministic Turing machines was originally proven by Stephen Cook in 1972. It was improved to its current form via a complex proof by Joel Seiferas, Michael Fischer, and Albert Meyer in 1978. Finally in 1983, Stanislav Žák achieved the same result with the simple proof taught today. The time hierarchy theorem for nondeterministic Turing machines states that if ''g''(''n'') is a time-constructible function, and ''f''(''n''+1) = o(''g''(''n'')), then :\mathsf(f(n)) \subsetneq \mathsf(g(n)). The analogous theorems for space are the space hierarchy theorems. A similar theorem is not known for time-bounded probabilistic complexity classes, unless the class also has one bit of advice.


Background

Both theorems use the notion of a time-constructible function. A function f:\mathbb\rightarrow\mathbb is time-constructible if there exists a deterministic
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer alg ...
such that for every n\in\mathbb, if the machine is started with an input of ''n'' ones, it will halt after precisely ''f''(''n'') steps. All
polynomial In mathematics, a polynomial is an expression consisting of indeterminates (also called variables) and coefficients, that involves only the operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and positive-integer powers of variables. An exampl ...
s with non-negative integer coefficients are time-constructible, as are exponential functions such as 2''n''.


Proof overview

We need to prove that some time class TIME(''g''(''n'')) is strictly larger than some time class TIME(''f''(''n'')). We do this by constructing a machine which cannot be in TIME(''f''(''n'')), by diagonalization. We then show that the machine is in TIME(''g''(''n'')), using a simulator machine.


Deterministic time hierarchy theorem


Statement

Time Hierarchy Theorem. If ''f''(''n'') is a time-constructible function, then there exists a
decision problem In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a decision problem is a computational problem that can be posed as a yes–no question of the input values. An example of a decision problem is deciding by means of an algorithm whe ...
which cannot be solved in worst-case deterministic time ''f''(''n'') but can be solved in worst-case deterministic time ''f''(''n'')2. In other words, :\mathsf(f(n)) \subsetneq \mathsf\left (f(n)^2 \right).
Note 1. ''f''(''n'') is at least ''n'', since smaller functions are never time-constructible.
Note 2. Even more generally, it can be shown that if ''f''(''n'') is time-constructible, then :\mathsf\left(o\left(\frac\right)\right)\subsetneq \mathsf\left (f(n) \right). For example, there are problems solvable in time ''n''2 but not time ''n'', since ''n'' is in :o\left(\frac\right).


Proof

We include here a proof that DTIME(''f''(''n'')) is a strict subset of DTIME(''f''(2''n'' + 1)3) as it is simpler. See the bottom of this section for information on how to extend the proof to ''f''(''n'')2. To prove this, we first define the language of the encodings of machines and their inputs which cause them to halt within f : H_f = \left\. Notice here that this is a time-class. It is the set of pairs of machines and inputs to those machines (''M'',''x'') to those machines so that the machine ''M'' accepts within ''f''(, ''x'', ) steps. Here, ''M'' is a deterministic Turing machine, and ''x'' is its input (the initial contents of its tape). 'M''denotes an input that encodes the Turing machine ''M''. Let ''m'' be the size of the tuple ( 'M'' ''x''). We know that we can decide membership of ''Hf'' by way of a deterministic Turing machine ''R'', that simulates ''M'' for ''f''(''x'') steps by first calculating ''f''(, ''x'', ) and then writing out a row of 0s of that length, and then using this row of 0s as a "clock" or "counter" to simulate ''M'' for at most that many steps. At each step, the simulating machine needs to look through the definition of ''M'' to decide what the next action would be. It is safe to say that this takes at most ''f''(''m'')3 operations (since it is known that a simulation of a machine of time complexity ''T''(''n'') can be achieved in time ''O(''T''log''T'')''), we have that: : H_f \in \mathsf\left(f(m)^3\right). The rest of the proof will show that : H_f \notin \mathsf\left(f\left( \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor \right)\right) so that if we substitute 2''n'' + 1 for ''m'', we get the desired result. Let us assume that ''Hf'' is in this time complexity class, and we will reach a contradiction. If ''Hf'' is in this time complexity class, then there exists a machine ''K'' which, given some machine description 'M''and input ''x'', decides whether the tuple ( 'M'' ''x'') is in ''Hf'' within :\mathsf\left(f\left( \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor \right)\right). We use this ''K'' to construct another machine, ''N'', which takes a machine description 'M''and runs ''K'' on the tuple ( 'M'' 'M'', ie. M is simulated on its own code by ''K'', and then ''N'' accepts if ''K'' rejects, and rejects if ''K'' accepts. If ''n'' is the length of the input to ''N'', then ''m'' (the length of the input to ''K'') is twice ''n'' plus some delimiter symbol, so ''m'' = 2''n'' + 1. ''N'''s running time is thus : \mathsf\left(f\left( \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor \right)\right) = \mathsf\left(f\left( \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor \right)\right) = \mathsf\left(f(n)\right). Now if we feed 'N''as input into ''N'' itself (which makes ''n'' the length of 'N'' and ask the question whether ''N'' accepts its own description as input, we get: * If ''N'' accepts 'N''(which we know it does in at most ''f''(''n'') operations since ''K'' halts on ( 'N'' 'N'' in ''f''(''n'') steps), this means that ''K'' rejects ( 'N'' 'N'', so ( 'N'' 'N'' is not in ''Hf'', and so by the definition of ''Hf'', this implies that ''N'' does not accept 'N''in ''f''(''n'') steps. Contradiction. * If ''N'' rejects 'N''(which we know it does in at most ''f''(''n'') operations), this means that ''K'' accepts ( 'N'' 'N'', so ( 'N'' 'N'' is in ''Hf'', and thus ''N'' does accept 'N''in ''f''(''n'') steps. Contradiction. We thus conclude that the machine ''K'' does not exist, and so : H_f \notin \mathsf\left(f\left( \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor \right)\right).


Extension

The reader may have realised that the proof is simpler because we have chosen a simple Turing machine simulation for which we can be certain that : H_f \in \mathsf(f(m)^3). It has been shownLuca Trevisan
Notes on Hierarchy Theorems
U.C. Berkeley
that a more efficient model of simulation exists which establishes that : H_f \in \mathsf(f(m) \log f(m)) but since this model of simulation is rather involved, it is not included here. Observe however that an identical argument as above then implies that DTIME(r(f(2m+1))) is not contained within DTIME(f(m)) if r(f(, M, +, x, )) is a function which gives a time within which it is possible to simulate a machine M with time complexity f(n) on input x.


Non-deterministic time hierarchy theorem

If ''g''(''n'') is a time-constructible function, and ''f''(''n''+1) = o(''g''(''n'')), then there exists a decision problem which cannot be solved in non-deterministic time ''f''(''n'') but can be solved in non-deterministic time ''g''(''n''). In other words, the complexity class NTIME(''f''(''n'')) is a strict subset of NTIME(''g''(''n'')).


Consequences

The time hierarchy theorems guarantee that the deterministic and non-deterministic versions of the exponential hierarchy are genuine hierarchies: in other words P
EXPTIME In computational complexity theory, the complexity class EXPTIME (sometimes called EXP or DEXPTIME) is the set of all decision problems that are solvable by a deterministic Turing machine in exponential time, i.e., in O(2''p''(''n'')) time, wh ...
2-EXP ⊊ ... and NPNEXPTIME ⊊ 2-NEXP ⊊ .... For example, \mathsf \subsetneq \mathsf since \mathsf \subseteq \mathsf (2^n)\subsetneq \mathsf (2^) \subseteq \mathsf. Indeed, \mathsf\left(2^n\right) \subseteq \mathsf\left(o\left(\frac\right)\right) \subsetneq \mathsf(2^) from the time hierarchy theorem. The theorem also guarantees that there are problems in P requiring arbitrarily large exponents to solve; in other words, P does not collapse to DTIME(''n''''k'') for any fixed ''k''. For example, there are problems solvable in ''n''5000 time but not ''n''4999 time. This is one argument against
Cobham's thesis Cobham's thesis, also known as Cobham–Edmonds thesis (named after Alan Cobham and Jack Edmonds),.. asserts that computational problems can be feasibly computed on some computational device only if they can be computed in polynomial time; that ...
, the convention that P is a practical class of algorithms. If such a collapse did occur, we could deduce that P ≠ PSPACE, since it is a well-known theorem that DTIME(''f''(''n'')) is strictly contained in DSPACE(''f''(''n'')). However, the time hierarchy theorems provide no means to relate deterministic and non-deterministic complexity, or time and space complexity, so they cast no light on the great unsolved questions of
computational complexity theory In theoretical computer science and mathematics, computational complexity theory focuses on classifying computational problems according to their resource usage, and relating these classes to each other. A computational problem is a task solved ...
: whether P and NP, NP and PSPACE, PSPACE and EXPTIME, or EXPTIME and NEXPTIME are equal or not.


See also

* Space hierarchy theorem


References

* Pages 310–313 of section 9.1: Hierarchy theorems. * Section 7.2: The Hierarchy Theorem, pp. 143–146. {{DEFAULTSORT:Time Hierarchy Theorem Structural complexity theory Theorems in computational complexity theory Articles containing proofs