HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, Tarski's theorem, proved by , states that in ZF the theorem "For every infinite set A, there is a bijective map between the sets A and A\times A" implies the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
. The opposite direction was already known, thus the theorem and axiom of choice are equivalent. Tarski told that when he tried to publish the theorem in Comptes Rendus de l'Académie des Sciences Paris, Fréchet and Lebesgue refused to present it. Fréchet wrote that an implication between two well known propositions is not a new result. Lebesgue wrote that an implication between two false propositions is of no interest.


Proof

The goal is to prove that the axiom of choice is implied by the statement "for every infinite set A: , A, = , A \times A, ". It is known that the well-ordering theorem is equivalent to the axiom of choice; thus it is enough to show that the statement implies that for every set B there exists a well-order. Since the collection of all ordinals such that there exists a surjective function from B to the ordinal is a set, there exists an infinite ordinal, \beta, such that there is no surjective function from B to \beta. We assume without loss of generality that the sets B and \beta are disjoint. By the initial assumption, , B \cup \beta, = , (B \cup \beta) \times (B \cup \beta), , thus there exists a
bijection In mathematics, a bijection, also known as a bijective function, one-to-one correspondence, or invertible function, is a function between the elements of two sets, where each element of one set is paired with exactly one element of the other ...
f : B \cup \beta \to (B \cup \beta) \times (B \cup \beta). For every x \in B, it is impossible that \beta \times \ \subseteq f because otherwise we could define a surjective function from B to \beta. Therefore, there exists at least one ordinal \gamma \in \beta such that f(\gamma) \in \beta \times \, so the set S_x = \ is not empty. We can define a new function: g(x) = \min S_x. This function is well defined since S_x is a non-empty set of ordinals, and so has a minimum. For every x, y \in B, x \neq y the sets S_x and S_y are disjoint. Therefore, we can define a well order on B, for every x, y \in B we define x \leq y \iff g(x) \leq g(y), since the image of g, that is, g /math> is a set of ordinals and therefore well ordered.


References

* * * {{Set theory Axiom of choice Cardinal numbers Set theory Theorems in the foundations of mathematics fr:Ordinal de Hartogs#Produit cardinal