Stromquist–Woodall Theorem
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The Stromquist–Woodall theorem is a theorem in
fair division Fair division is the problem in game theory of dividing a set of resources among several people who have an entitlement to them so that each person receives their due share. That problem arises in various real-world settings such as division of inh ...
and measure theory. Informally, it says that, for any cake, for any ''n'' people with different tastes, and for any fraction ''w'', there exists a subset of the cake that all people value at exactly a fraction ''w'' of the total cake value, and it can be cut using at most 2n-2 cuts. The theorem is about a circular 1-dimensional cake (a "pie"). Formally, it can be described as the interval ,1in which the two endpoints are identified. There are ''n'' continuous measures over the cake: V_1,\ldots,V_n; each measure represents the valuations of a different person over subsets of the cake. The theorem says that, for every weight w \in ,1/math>, there is a subset C_w, which all people value at exactly w: : \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, V_i(C_w)=w, where C_w is a union of at most n-1 intervals. This means that 2n-2 cuts are sufficient for cutting the subset C_w. If the cake is not circular (that is, the endpoints are not identified), then C_w may be the union of up to n intervals, in case one interval is adjacent to 0 and one other interval is adjacent to 1.


Proof sketch

Let W \subseteq ,1/math> be the subset of all weights for which the theorem is true. Then: # 1 \in W. Proof: take C_1 := C (recall that the value measures are normalized such that all partners value the entire cake as 1). # If w\in W, then also 1-w \in W. Proof: take C_ := C\smallsetminus C_w. If C_w is a union of n-1 intervals in a circle, then C_ is also a union of n-1 intervals. # W is a closed set. This is easy to prove, since the space of unions of n-1 intervals is a
compact set In mathematics, specifically general topology, compactness is a property that seeks to generalize the notion of a closed and bounded subset of Euclidean space by making precise the idea of a space having no "punctures" or "missing endpoints", i. ...
under a suitable topology. # If w\in W, then also w/2 \in W. This is the most interesting part of the proof; see below. From 1-4, it follows that W= ,1/math>. In other words, the theorem is valid for ''every'' possible weight.


Proof sketch for part 4

* Assume that C_w is a union of n-1 intervals and that all n partners value it as exactly w. * Define the following function on the cake, f: C \to \mathbb^n: :: f(t) = (t, t^2, \ldots, t^n)\,\,\,\,\,\,t\in ,1/math> * Define the following measures on \mathbb^n: :: U_i(Y) = V_i(f^(Y) \cap C_w)\,\,\,\,\,\,\,\,\, Y\subseteq \mathbb^n * Note that f^(\mathbb^n) = C. Hence, for every partner i: U_i(\mathbb^n) = w. * Hence, by the
Stone–Tukey theorem In mathematical measure theory, for every positive integer the ham sandwich theorem states that given measurable "objects" in -dimensional Euclidean space, it is possible to divide each one of them in half (with respect to their measure, e.g. ...
, there is a hyper-plane that cuts \mathbb^n to two half-spaces, H, H', such that: :: \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, U_i(H)=U_i(H')=w/2 * Define M=f^(H)\cap C_w and M'=f^(H')\cap C_w. Then, by the definition of the U_i: :: \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, V_i(M)=V_i(M')=w/2 * The set C_w has n-1 connected components (intervals). Hence, its image f(C_w) also has n-1 connected components (1-dimensional curves in \mathbb^n). * The hyperplane that forms the boundary between H and H' intersects f(C_w) in at most n points. Hence, the total number of connected components (curves) in H\cap f(C_w) and H'\cap f(C_w) is 2n-1. Hence, one of these must have at most n-1 components. * Suppose it is H that has at most n-1 components (curves). Hence, M has at most n-1 components (intervals). * Hence, we can take C_=M. This proves that w\in W.


Tightness proof

Stromquist and Woodall prove that the number n-1 is tight if the weight w is either irrational, or rational with a reduced fraction r/s such that s\geq n.


Proof sketch for w=1/n

* Choose (n-1)(n+1) equally-spaced points along the circle; call them P_1,\ldots,P_. * Define n-1 measures in the following way. Measure i is concentrated in small neighbourhoods of the following (n+1) points: P_,P_,\ldots,P_. So, near each point P_, there is a fraction 1/(n+1) of the measure u_i. * Define the n-th measure as proportional to the length measure. * Every subset whose consensus value is 1/n, must touch at least two points for each of the first n-1 measures (since the value near each single point is 1/(n+1) which is slightly less than the required 1/n). Hence, it must touch at least 2(n-1) points. * On the other hand, every subset whose consensus value is 1/n, must have total length 1/n (because of the n-th measure). The number of "gaps" between the points is 1/\big((n+1)(n-1)\big); hence the subset can contain at most n-1 gaps. * The consensus subset must touch 2(n-1) points but contain at most n-1 gaps; hence it must contain at least n-1 intervals.


See also

*
Fair cake-cutting Fair cake-cutting is a kind of fair division problem. The problem involves a ''heterogeneous'' resource, such as a cake with different toppings, that is assumed to be ''divisible'' – it is possible to cut arbitrarily small pieces of it without ...
* Fair pie-cutting *
Exact division Exact division, also called consensus division, is a partition of a continuous resource ("fair cake-cutting, cake") into some ''k'' pieces, such that each of ''n'' people with different tastes agree on the value of each of the pieces. For example, c ...
*
Stone–Tukey theorem In mathematical measure theory, for every positive integer the ham sandwich theorem states that given measurable "objects" in -dimensional Euclidean space, it is possible to divide each one of them in half (with respect to their measure, e.g. ...


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stromquist-Woodall theorem Cake-cutting Theorems in measure theory