HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from prem ...
, a strict conditional (symbol: \Box, or ⥽) is a conditional governed by a modal operator, that is, a
logical connective In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. They can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the binary ...
of
modal logic Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend ot ...
. It is logically equivalent to the
material conditional The material conditional (also known as material implication) is an operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \rightarrow is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \rightarrow Q is true unless P is true and Q i ...
of classical logic, combined with the necessity operator from
modal logic Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend ot ...
. For any two
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
s ''p'' and ''q'', the
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
''p'' → ''q'' says that ''p'' materially implies ''q'' while \Box (p \rightarrow q) says that ''p'' strictly implies ''q''. Strict conditionals are the result of Clarence Irving Lewis's attempt to find a conditional for logic that can adequately express
indicative conditional In natural languages, an indicative conditional is a conditional sentence such as "If Leona is at home, she isn't in Paris", whose grammatical form restricts it to discussing what could be true. Indicatives are typically defined in opposition to co ...
s in natural language. They have also been used in studying
Molinist Molinism, named after 16th-century Spanish Jesuit priest and Roman Catholic theologian Luis de Molina, is the thesis that God has middle knowledge. It seeks to reconcile the apparent tension of divine providence and human free will. Prominent ...
theology.


Avoiding paradoxes

The strict conditionals may avoid
paradoxes of material implication The paradoxes of material implication are a group of true formulae involving material conditionals whose translations into natural language are intuitively false when the conditional is translated as "if ... then ...". A material conditional formu ...
. The following statement, for example, is not correctly formalized by material implication: : If Bill Gates has graduated in Medicine, then Elvis never died. This condition should clearly be false: the degree of Bill Gates has nothing to do with whether Elvis is still alive. However, the direct encoding of this formula in
classical logic Classical logic (or standard logic or Frege-Russell logic) is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy. Characteristics Each logical system in this class ...
using material implication leads to: : Bill Gates graduated in Medicine → Elvis never died. This formula is true because whenever the antecedent ''A'' is false, a formula ''A'' → ''B'' is true. Hence, this formula is not an adequate translation of the original sentence. An encoding using the strict conditional is: : \Box (Bill Gates graduated in Medicine → Elvis never died.) In modal logic, this formula means (roughly) that, in every possible world in which Bill Gates graduated in Medicine, Elvis never died. Since one can easily imagine a world where Bill Gates is a Medicine graduate and Elvis is dead, this formula is false. Hence, this formula seems to be a correct translation of the original sentence.


Problems

Although the strict conditional is much closer to being able to express natural language conditionals than the material conditional, it has its own problems with
consequent A consequent is the second half of a hypothetical proposition. In the standard form of such a proposition, it is the part that follows "then". In an implication, if ''P'' implies ''Q'', then ''P'' is called the antecedent and ''Q'' is called ...
s that are necessarily true (such as 2 + 2 = 4) or antecedents that are necessarily false. The following sentence, for example, is not correctly formalized by a strict conditional: : If Bill Gates graduated in Medicine, then 2 + 2 = 4. Using strict conditionals, this sentence is expressed as: : \Box (Bill Gates graduated in Medicine → 2 + 2 = 4) In modal logic, this formula means that, in every possible world where Bill Gates graduated in medicine, it holds that 2 + 2 = 4. Since 2 + 2 is equal to 4 in all possible worlds, this formula is true, although it does not seem that the original sentence should be. A similar situation arises with 2 + 2 = 5, which is necessarily false: : If 2 + 2 = 5, then Bill Gates graduated in Medicine. Some logicians view this situation as indicating that the strict conditional is still unsatisfactory. Others have noted that the strict conditional cannot adequately express
counterfactual conditional Counterfactual conditionals (also ''subjunctive'' or ''X-marked'') are conditional sentences which discuss what would have been true under different circumstances, e.g. "If Peter believed in ghosts, he would be afraid to be here." Counterfactua ...
s, and that it does not satisfy certain logical properties. In particular, the strict conditional is transitive, while the counterfactual conditional is not. Some logicians, such as
Paul Grice Herbert Paul Grice (13 March 1913 – 28 August 1988), usually publishing under the name H. P. Grice, H. Paul Grice, or Paul Grice, was a British philosopher of language. He is best known for his theory of implicature and the cooperative pri ...
, have used
conversational implicature In pragmatics, a subdiscipline of linguistics, an implicature is something the speaker suggests or implies with an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed. Implicatures can aid in communicating more efficiently than by explicitly sayi ...
to argue that, despite apparent difficulties, the material conditional is just fine as a translation for the natural language 'if...then...'. Others still have turned to
relevance logic Relevance logic, also called relevant logic, is a kind of non-classical logic requiring the antecedent and consequent of implications to be relevantly related. They may be viewed as a family of substructural or modal logics. It is generally, but ...
to supply a connection between the antecedent and consequent of provable conditionals.


Constructive logic

In a
constructive Although the general English usage of the adjective constructive is "helping to develop or improve something; helpful to someone, instead of upsetting and negative," as in the phrase "constructive criticism," in legal writing ''constructive'' has ...
setting, the symmetry between ⥽ and \Box is broken, and the two connectives can be studied independently. Constructive strict implication can be used to investigate
interpretability In mathematical logic, interpretability is a relation between formal theories that expresses the possibility of interpreting or translating one into the other. Informal definition Assume ''T'' and ''S'' are formal theories. Slightly simplified, ' ...
of
Heyting arithmetic In mathematical logic, Heyting arithmetic is an axiomatization of arithmetic in accordance with the philosophy of intuitionism.Troelstra 1973:18 It is named after Arend Heyting, who first proposed it. Axiomatization As with first-order Peano ar ...
and to model arrows and guarded
recursion Recursion (adjective: ''recursive'') occurs when a thing is defined in terms of itself or of its type. Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from linguistics to logic. The most common application of recursion is in mathematic ...
in computer science.


See also

* Corresponding conditional *
Counterfactual conditional Counterfactual conditionals (also ''subjunctive'' or ''X-marked'') are conditional sentences which discuss what would have been true under different circumstances, e.g. "If Peter believed in ghosts, he would be afraid to be here." Counterfactua ...
*
Dynamic semantics Dynamic semantics is a framework in logic and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context. In static semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true; in dynam ...
* Import-Export *
Indicative conditional In natural languages, an indicative conditional is a conditional sentence such as "If Leona is at home, she isn't in Paris", whose grammatical form restricts it to discussing what could be true. Indicatives are typically defined in opposition to co ...
*
Logical consequence Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic, which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A valid logical argument is on ...
*
Material conditional The material conditional (also known as material implication) is an operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \rightarrow is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \rightarrow Q is true unless P is true and Q i ...


References


Bibliography

*Edgington, Dorothy, 2001, "Conditionals," in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. *For an introduction to non-classical logic as an attempt to find a better translation of the conditional, see: ** Priest, Graham, 2001. ''An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic''. Cambridge Univ. Press. *For an extended philosophical discussion of the issues mentioned in this article, see: ** Mark Sainsbury, 2001. ''Logical Forms''. Blackwell Publishers. * Jonathan Bennett, 2003. ''A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals''. Oxford Univ. Press. {{Formal semantics Conditionals Logical connectives Modal logic Necessity Linguistic modality Formal semantics (natural language)