HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The ''Sophist'' ( el, Σοφιστής; la, Sophista Henri Estienne (ed.), ''Platonis opera quae extant omnia'', Vol. 1, 1578
p. 217
) is a
Platonic dialogue Socratic dialogue ( grc, Σωκρατικὸς λόγος) is a genre of literary prose developed in Greece at the turn of the fourth century BC. The earliest ones are preserved in the works of Plato and Xenophon and all involve Socrates as the p ...
from the philosopher's late period, most likely written in 360 BC. In it the interlocutors, led by Eleatic Stranger employ the method of division in order to classify and define the
sophist A sophist ( el, σοφιστής, sophistes) was a teacher in ancient Greece in the fifth and fourth centuries BC. Sophists specialized in one or more subject areas, such as philosophy, rhetoric, music, athletics, and mathematics. They taught ...
and describe his essential attributes and differentia vis a vis the philosopher and statesman. Like its sequel, the '' Statesman'', the dialogue is unusual in that Socrates is present but plays only a minor role. Instead, the Eleatic Stranger takes the lead in the discussion. Because Socrates is silent, it is difficult to attribute the views put forward by the Eleatic Stranger to Plato, beyond the difficulty inherent in taking any character to be an author's "mouthpiece".


Background

The main objective of the dialogue is to identify what a
sophist A sophist ( el, σοφιστής, sophistes) was a teacher in ancient Greece in the fifth and fourth centuries BC. Sophists specialized in one or more subject areas, such as philosophy, rhetoric, music, athletics, and mathematics. They taught ...
is and how a sophist differs from a philosopher and statesman. Because each seems distinguished by a particular form of knowledge, the dialogue continues some of the lines of inquiry pursued in the epistemological dialogue, '' Theaetetus'', which is said to have taken place the day before. Because the ''Sophist'' treats these matters, it is often taken to shed light on Plato's Theory of Forms and is compared with the '' Parmenides'', which criticized what is often taken to be the theory of forms. In
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
, contemporary or slightly preceding the Republic, Plato poses the problem, decisive for the use of dialectics for cognitive purposes, of the relationship between name and thing, between word and reality. Thus the ‘Sophist’ has its major background in the
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
. This dialogue is resolved in a contrast between the thesis of Hermogenes, who considers the name a simple sequence of sounds conventionally chosen to refer to an object, and the thesis of Cratylus, a pupil of the old Heraclitus, who supported the full expression of the essence of the “nominatum” in the name, and who considered the names as expressions forged by an Onomaturge, capable of expressing the essence of the thing named. Following this research, all the ‘Sophist’ is dedicated to find the right definition of the name “sophist”. Some contemporary scholars, based on their orientations, have argued that in the
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
Plato gave his assent now to the thesis of Hermogenes, now to the thesis of Cratylus.
Gérard Genette Gérard Genette (7 June 1930 – 11 May 2018) was a French literary theorist, associated in particular with the structuralist movement and such figures as Roland Barthes and Claude Lévi-Strauss, from whom he adapted the concept of ''bricolage ...
, in the work ‘Mimologique. Voyage en Cratilie’ (1976), starts from Plato's speech to argue the idea of arbitrariness of the sign: according to this thesis, already supported by the great linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, the connection between language and objects is not natural, but culturally determined. The ideas developed in the
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
, although dated, have historically been an important point of reference in the development of Linguistics. On the basis of the
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
,
Gaetano Licata Gaetano (anglicized '' Cajetan'') is an Italian masculine given name. It is also used as a surname. It is derived from the Latin ''Caietanus'', meaning "from ''Caieta''" (the modern Gaeta). The given name has been in use in Italy since medieval ...
has reconstructed, in the essay ‘Plato’s theory of language. Perspectives on the concept of truth’ (2007, Il Melangolo), the relationship between the
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
and the ‘Sophist’ and the Platonic conception of semantics, according to which names have a natural link, (an essential foundation) with their "nominatum". This author argues that Plato accepts Cratylus' thesis. Finally, the concept of language and of “true discourse” of
Cratylus Cratylus ( ; grc, Κρατύλος, ''Kratylos'') was an ancient Athenian philosopher from the mid-late 5th century BCE, known mostly through his portrayal in Plato's dialogue '' Cratylus''. He was a radical proponent of Heraclitean philosophy ...
will be very important for the study of diairetic dialectic in the ‘Sophist’.


Introduction

This dialogue takes place a day after Plato's ''Theaetetus'' in an unspecified gymnasium in Athens. The participants are Socrates, who plays a minor role, the elder mathematician Theodorus, the young mathematician Theaetetus, and a visitor from Elea, the hometown of Parmenides and
Zeno Zeno ( grc, Ζήνων) may refer to: People * Zeno (name), including a list of people and characters with the name Philosophers * Zeno of Elea (), philosopher, follower of Parmenides, known for his paradoxes * Zeno of Citium (333 – 264 BC), ...
, who is often referred to in English translations as the Eleatic Stranger or the Eleatic Visitor. Other young mathematicians are also silently present. The dialogue begins when Socrates arrives and asks the Eleatic Stranger, whether in his homeland, the sophist, statesperson, and philosopher are considered to be one kind or three. The Eleatic Stranger responds that they are three and then sets about to give an account of the sophist through dialectical exchange with Theaetetus.


Method of definition (216a–236d)

The Eleatic Stranger pursues a different definition than features in Plato's other dialogues by using a model, comparing the model with the target kind, collection, and division (''diairesis'') of the collected kinds. At first, he starts using a mundane model (a fisherman), which shares some qualities in common with the target kind (the sophist). This common quality is the certain expertise ('' techne'') in one subject. Then through the method of collection of different kinds (farming, caring for mortal bodies, for things that are put together or fabricated and imitation), he tries to bring them together into one kind, which he calls ''productive art''. The same is true with the collection of learning, recognition, commerce, combat and hunting, which can be grouped into the kind of ''acquisitive art''. After these two collections, he proceeds to the division of the types of expertise into ''production'' and ''acquisition''. Then he tries to find out to which of these two sub-kinds the fisherman belongs (classification) case, the acquisitive kind of expertise. By following the same method, namely, diairesis through collection, he divides the acquisitive art into ''possession taking'' and ''exchanging goods'', to which sophistry belongs. The sophist is a kind of merchant. After many successive collections and divisions he finally arrives at the definition of the model (fisherman). Throughout this process the Eleatic Stranger classifies many kinds of activities (hunting, aquatic-hunting, fishing, strike-hunting). After the verbal explanation of the model (definition), he tries to find out what the model and the target kind share in common (sameness) and what differentiates them (difference). Through this comparison, and after having been aware of the different kinds and sub-kinds, he can classify sophistry also among the other branches of the ‘tree’ of division of expertise as follows: "1. production, hunting by persuasion and money-earning, 2. acquisition, soul wholesaling, 3. soul retailing, retailing things that others make, 4. soul retailing, retailing things that he makes himself, 5. possession taking, competition, money-making expertise in debating." Throughout the process of comparison of the distinguished kinds through his method of collection, the Eleatic Stranger discovers some attributes in relation to which the kinds can be divided (difference in relation to something). These are similar to the ''
Categories Category, plural categories, may refer to: Philosophy and general uses *Categorization, categories in cognitive science, information science and generally *Category of being * ''Categories'' (Aristotle) * Category (Kant) *Categories (Peirce) * ...
'' of Aristotle, so to say: quantity, quality, relation, location, time, position, end, etc. After having failed to define sophistry, the Stranger attempts a final diairesis through the collection of the five definitions of sophistry. Since these five definitions share in common one quality (sameness), which is the ''imitation'', he finally qualifies sophistry as ''imitation art''. Following the division of the imitation art in ''copy-making and appearance-making'', he discovers that sophistry falls under the ''appearance-making art'', namely the Sophist imitates the wise man. The sophist is presented negatively, but he can be said to be someone who merely pretends to have knowledge or to be a purveyor of false knowledge only if
right opinion Platonism is the philosophy of Plato and philosophical systems closely derived from it, though contemporary platonists do not necessarily accept all of the doctrines of Plato. Platonism had a profound effect on Western thought. Platonism at le ...
and false opinion can be distinguished. It seems impossible to say that the sophist presents things that are not as though they were, or passes off "non-being" as "being," since this would suggest that non-being exists, or that non-existence exists. Otherwise, the sophist couldn't "do" anything with it. The Stranger suggests that it is Parmenides' doctrine of being and non-being that is at the root of this problem, and so proceeds to criticize Parmenides' ideas, namely that "it is impossible that things that are not are."


Puzzles of being and not-being, great kinds (236d–264b)

The Eleatic Stranger, before proceeding to the final definition of sophistry, has to make clear the concepts that he used throughout the procedure of definition. In other words, he has to clarify what is the nature of the
Being In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into categories and which of these entities exi ...
(''that which is''), Not-Being, sameness (identity), difference, motion (change), and rest, and how they are interrelated. Therefore, he examines Parmenides’ notion in comparison with Empedocles and Heraclitus’ in order to find out whether Being is identical with ''change'' or ''rest'', or both. The conclusion is that rest and change both "are," that is, both are beings; Parmenides had said that only rest "is." Furthermore, ''Being'' is a "kind" that all existing things share in common. ''Sameness'' is a "kind" that all things which belong to the same kind or genus share with reference to a certain attribute, and due to which diaeresis through collection is possible. ''Difference'' is a "kind" that makes things of the same genus distinct from one another; therefore it enables us to proceed to their division. Finally, so-called ''Not-Being'' is not the opposite of Being, but simply different from it. Therefore, the negation of Being is identified with "difference." Not-being is difference, not the opposite of Being. Following these conclusions, the true statement can be distinguished from the false one, since each statement consists of a verb and a name. The name refers to the subject, and because a thought or a speech is always about something, and it cannot be about nothing (''Non-Being''). The verb is the sign of the action that the subject performs or the action being performed to or on the subject. When the verb states something that is about the subject, namely one of his properties, then the statement is true. While when the verb states something that is ''different'' (''it is not'') from the properties of the subject, then the statement is false, but is not attributing being to non-being. It is plausible then, that ‘''things that are not (appearing and seeming) somehow are''’, and so it is also plausible that the sophist produces false appearances and imitates the wise man.


Final definition (264b–268d)

After having solved all these puzzles, that is to say the interrelation between being, not-being, difference and negation, as well as the possibility of the "appearing and seeming but not really being," the Eleatic Stranger can finally proceed to define sophistry. "Sophistry is a productive art, human, of the imitation kind, copy-making, of the appearance-making kind, uninformed and insincere in the form of contrary-speech-producing art."


Texts and translations

*''Plato: Theaetetus, Sophist.'' Greek with translation by Harold N. Fowler. Loeb Classical Library 123. Harvard Univ. Press (originally published 1921).
HUP listing
*Fowler translation a
Perseus
Translated by Benjamin Jowett **Jowett translation also available a
StandardEbooks
*Plato. ''Opera'', volume I. Oxford Classical Texts. *Plato. ''Complete Works.'' Hackett, 1997.


Notes


References

*Ackrill, J. L. 1997. ''Essays on Plato and Aristotle.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press. *Ambuel, David. 2007. ''Image and Paradigm in Plato's Sophist''. Parmenides Publishing. *Bakalis, N. 2005. ''Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments'' *Benardete, S. 1986. ''Plato's Sophist. Part II of The Being of the Beautiful.'' Chicago: Chicago University Press. * Cornford, F. M. 1935. ''Plato's Theory of Knowledge.'' London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. *Eck, J. van. 2002. “Not Being and Difference: on Plato's Sophist 256d5-258e3." ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'' 23: 63-84. *Frede, M. 1992. “Plato's Sophist on False Statements.” In ''The Cambridge Companion to Plato.'' Edited by Richard Kraut, 397-424. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. *Frede, M. 1996. “The Literary Form of the Sophist.” In ''Form and Argument in Late Plato'' Edited by C. Gill and M. M. McCabe, 135-151. Oxford: Clarendon Press. *Gill, C. and M. M. McCabe eds. 1996. ''Form and Argument in Late Plato.'' Oxford: Clarendon Press. *Harte, V. 2002. ''Plato on Parts and Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure'', Oxford: Clarendon Press. * Heidegger, M. 1997. Plato's Sophist. Translated by Richard Rojcewicz and André Schuwer. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press. *Moravcsik, J. M. E. 1992. ''Plato and Platonism.'' Oxford: Blackwell. *Nehamas, A. 1982. “Participation and Predication in Plato's Later Thought.” ''Review of Metaphysics'' 26: 343-74. *Gaetano Licata, ''Teoria platonica del linguaggio. Prospettive sul concetto di verità'', Il Melangolo, Genova 2007. * Sallis, J. 1996. ''Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues.'' Bloomington: Indiana University Press. * Plato. 1996. ''Plato's Sophist. The Professor of Wisdom: With Translation, Introduction and Glossary by Eva Brann, Peter Kalkavage, Eric Salem.'' Newburyport: Focus Publishing. *Stenzel, J. 1940
931 Year 931 ( CMXXXI) was a common year starting on Saturday (link will display the full calendar) of the Julian calendar. Events By place Europe * Spring – Hugh of Provence, king of Italy, cedes Lower Burgundy to Rudolph II, in ...
''Plato's Method of Dialectic.'' Translated and Edited by D. J. Allan. Oxford: Clarendon Press. * Vlastos, G. 1973. “An Ambiguity in the Sophist”, in ''Platonic Studies'' Edited by G. Vlastos, 270-322. Princeton: Princeton University Press. *White, N. P. 1993. ''Plato: Sophist'', Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett.


External links

* * Greek text of the dialogue a
Perseus
* *

* ttps://www.ontology.co/biblio/plato-sophist-biblio-one.htm Plato's ''Sophist'', Annotated Bibliography of the studies in English {{Authority control Dialogues of Plato Metaphysics literature Epistemology literature