HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In philosophical logic, a slingshot argument is one of a group of arguments claiming to show that all
true True most commonly refers to truth, the state of being in congruence with fact or reality. True may also refer to: Places * True, West Virginia, an unincorporated community in the United States * True, Wisconsin, a town in the United States * ...
sentences stand for the same thing. This type of argument was dubbed the " slingshot" by philosophers
Jon Barwise Kenneth Jon Barwise (; June 29, 1942 – March 5, 2000) was an American mathematician, philosopher and logician who proposed some fundamental revisions to the way that logic is understood and used. Education and career Born in Independence, ...
and John Perry (1981) due to its disarming simplicity. It is usually said that versions of the slingshot argument have been given by
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic ph ...
,
Alonzo Church Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American mathematician, computer scientist, logician, philosopher, professor and editor who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer scien ...
, W. V. Quine, and Donald Davidson. However, it has been disputed by Lorenz Krüger (1995) that there is much unity in this tradition. Moreover, Krüger rejects Davidson's claim that the argument can refute the correspondence theory of truth. Stephen Neale (1995) claims, controversially, that the most compelling version was suggested by Kurt Gödel (1944). These arguments are sometimes modified to support the alternative, and evidently stronger, conclusion that there is only one '' fact'', or one true ''
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
'', '' state of affairs'', ''
truth condition In semantics and pragmatics, a truth condition is the condition under which a sentence is true. For example, "It is snowing in Nebraska" is true precisely when it is snowing in Nebraska. Truth conditions of a sentence do not necessarily reflect cu ...
'', ''
truthmaker Truthmaker theory is "the branch of metaphysics that explores the relationships between what is true and what exists". The basic intuition behind truthmaker theory is that truth depends on being. For example, a perceptual experience of a green tre ...
'', and so on.


The argument

One version of the argument (Perry 1996) proceeds as follows. Assumptions: # Substitution. If two terms designate the same thing, then substituting one for another in a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence. # Redistribution. Rearranging the parts of a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence, provided the truth conditions of the sentence do not change. # Every sentence is equivalent to a sentence of the form ''F''(''a''). In other words, every sentence has the same designation as some sentence that attributes a property to something. (For example, "All men are mortal" is equivalent to "The number 1 has the property of being such that all men are mortal".) # For any two objects there is a relation that holds uniquely between them. (For example, if the objects in question are denoted by "''a''" and "''b''", the relation in question might be ''R''(''x'', ''y''), which is stipulated to hold just in case ''x'' = ''a'' and ''y'' = ''b''.) Let ''S'' and ''T'' be arbitrary true sentences, designating ''Des''(''S'') and ''Des''(''T''), respectively. (No assumptions are made about what kinds of things ''Des''(''S'') and ''Des''(''T'') are.) It is now shown by a series of designation-preserving transformations that ''Des''(''S'') = ''Des''(''T''). Here, "\iota x" can be read as "the ''x'' such that". Note that (1)-(9) is not a derivation of ''T'' from ''S''. Rather, it is a series of (allegedly) designation-preserving transformation steps.


Responses to the argument

As Gödel (1944) observed, the slingshot argument does not go through if
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, philosopher, logician, and public intellectual. He had a considerable influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, linguistics, ...
's famous account of
definite description In formal semantics and philosophy of language, a definite description is a denoting phrase in the form of "the X" where X is a noun-phrase or a singular common noun. The definite description is ''proper'' if X applies to a unique individual or o ...
s is assumed. Russell claimed that the proper logical interpretation of a sentence of the form "The ''F'' is ''G''" is: : Exactly one thing is ''F'', and that thing is also ''G''. Or, in the language of
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
: : \exists x (\forall y (F(y) \leftrightarrow y = x) \land G(x)) When the sentences above containing \iota-expressions are expanded out to their proper form, the steps involving substitution are seen to be illegitimate. Consider, for example, the move from (3) to (4). On Russell's account, (3) and (4) are shorthand for: Clearly the substitution principle and assumption 4 do not license the move from (3') to (4'). Thus, one way to look at the slingshot is as simply another argument in favor of Russell's theory of definite descriptions. If one is not willing to accept Russell's theory, then it seems wise to challenge either ''substitution'' or ''redistribution'', which seem to be the other weakest points in the argument. Perry (1996), for example, rejects both of these principles, proposing to replace them with certain weaker, qualified versions that do not allow the slingshot argument to go through. An Italian philosopher, Gaetano Licata, in 2011 rejected the slingshot argument, showing that the concept of identity (=) employed in Davidson and Gödel's demonstration is very problematic, because Gödel (following Russell) uses the G. W. Leibniz's principle of the
identity of indiscernibles The identity of indiscernibles is an ontological principle that states that there cannot be separate objects or entities that have all their properties in common. That is, entities ''x'' and ''y'' are identical if every predicate possessed by ''x'' ...
, which suffer from the criticism proposed by
Ludwig Wittgenstein Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein ( ; ; 26 April 1889 – 29 April 1951) was an Austrian-British philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language. He is con ...
: to state that x=y when all properties of x are also properties of y is false because y and x are different signs, while to state that x=x when all properties of x are also properties of x is a nonsense.{{page needed, date=April 2018 Licata's thesis is that the sign = (usually employed between numbers) needs a logical foundation before being employed between objects and properties.


See also

* Abstraction *
Logic of information The logic of information, or the logical theory of information, considers the information content of logical signs and expressions along the lines initially developed by Charles Sanders Peirce. In this line of work, the concept of information serve ...
*
Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography This Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography consolidates numerous references to the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, including letters, manuscripts, publications, and . For an extensive chronological list of Peirce's works (titled in English), s ...


References

* Barwise, K. J. & Perry, John (1981), "Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations", ''Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Language'', VI. * Gödel, Kurt (1944), "Russell's mathematical logic", in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), ''The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell'', Evanston and Chicago: Northwestern University Press, pp. 125–53. * Krüger, Lorenz (1995), "Has the correspondence theory of truth been refuted?", ''European Journal of Philosophy'', vol. 3, 157–173, repr. in Lorenz Krüger, ''Why Does History Matter to Philosophy and the Sciences?'', ed. by Thomas Sturm, Wolfgang Carl, and Lorraine Daston. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2005, pp. 201–217. * Licata, Gaetano (2011), ''Truth and Facts: Rejection of the Slingshot Argument in Defence of the Correspondence Theory of Truth'', Rome, Aracne. * Neale, Stephen (1995), "The philosophical significance of Gödel's Slingshot", ''Mind'', vol. 104, no. 416, pp. 761–825. * Peirce, C. S. (1906), "Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism", ''The Monist'', 16, 492–546 (1906). Reprinted, ''Collected Papers'', CP 4.530–572
Eprint
* Perry, John (1996), "Evading the slingshot", in
Andy Clark Andy Clark, (born 1957) is a British philosopher who is Professor of Cognitive Philosophy at the University of Sussex. Prior to this, he was at professor of philosophy and Chair in Logic and Metaphysics at the University of Edinburgh in Sc ...
et al. (eds.), ''Philosophy and Cognitive Science''
PDF


External links


Stephen Neale's ''Facing Facts'' reviewed by John Macfarlane


Philosophy of language Philosophical arguments Philosophical logic