HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, there is an ample supply of categorical dualities between certain categories of
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
s and categories of
partially ordered set In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
s. Today, these dualities are usually collected under the label Stone duality, since they form a natural generalization of
Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first ha ...
. These concepts are named in honor of Marshall Stone. Stone-type dualities also provide the foundation for
pointless topology In mathematics, pointless topology, also called point-free topology (or pointfree topology) or topology without points and locale theory, is an approach to topology that avoids mentioning point (mathematics), points, and in which the Lattice (order ...
and are exploited in
theoretical computer science Theoretical computer science is a subfield of computer science and mathematics that focuses on the Abstraction, abstract and mathematical foundations of computation. It is difficult to circumscribe the theoretical areas precisely. The Associati ...
for the study of formal semantics. This article gives pointers to special cases of Stone duality and explains a very general instance thereof in detail.


Overview of Stone-type dualities

Probably the most general duality that is classically referred to as "Stone duality" is the duality between the category Sob of
sober space In mathematics, a sober space is a topological space ''X'' such that every (nonempty) irreducible space, irreducible closed subset of ''X'' is the closure (topology), closure of exactly one point of ''X'': that is, every nonempty irreducible close ...
s with
continuous function In mathematics, a continuous function is a function such that a small variation of the argument induces a small variation of the value of the function. This implies there are no abrupt changes in value, known as '' discontinuities''. More preci ...
s and the category SFrm of spatial frames with appropriate frame homomorphisms. The
dual category In category theory, a branch of mathematics, the opposite category or dual category C^ of a given Category (mathematics), category C is formed by reversing the morphisms, i.e. interchanging the source and target of each morphism. Doing the reversal ...
of SFrm is the category of spatial locales denoted by SLoc. The categorical equivalence of Sob and SLoc is the basis for the mathematical area of
pointless topology In mathematics, pointless topology, also called point-free topology (or pointfree topology) or topology without points and locale theory, is an approach to topology that avoids mentioning point (mathematics), points, and in which the Lattice (order ...
, which is devoted to the study of Loc—the category of all locales, of which SLoc is a
full subcategory In mathematics, specifically category theory, a subcategory of a category ''C'' is a category ''S'' whose objects are objects in ''C'' and whose morphisms are morphisms in ''C'' with the same identities and composition of morphisms. Intuitivel ...
. The involved constructions are characteristic for this kind of duality, and are detailed below. Now one can easily obtain a number of other dualities by restricting to certain special classes of sober spaces: * The category CohSp of coherent spaces (and coherent maps) is equivalent to the category CohLoc of coherent (or spectral) locales (and coherent maps), on the assumption of the
Boolean prime ideal theorem In mathematics, the Boolean prime ideal theorem states that Ideal (order theory), ideals in a Boolean algebra (structure), Boolean algebra can be extended to Ideal (order theory)#Prime ideals , prime ideals. A variation of this statement for Filte ...
(in fact, this statement is equivalent to that assumption). The significance of this result stems from the fact that CohLoc in turn is dual to the category DLat01 of bounded distributive lattices. Hence, DLat01 is dual to CohSp—one obtains Stone's representation theorem for distributive lattices. * When restricting further to coherent spaces that are Hausdorff, one obtains the category Stone of so-called Stone spaces. On the side of DLat01, the restriction yields the subcategory Bool of Boolean algebras. Thus one obtains
Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first ha ...
. * Stone's representation for distributive lattices can be extended via an equivalence of coherent spaces and Priestley spaces (ordered topological spaces, that are
compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact, a type of agreement used by U.S. states * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a t ...
and totally order-disconnected). One obtains a representation of distributive lattices via ordered topologies: Priestley's representation theorem for distributive lattices. Many other Stone-type dualities could be added to these basic dualities.


Duality of sober spaces and spatial locales


The lattice of open sets

The starting point for the theory is the fact that every topological space is characterized by a set of points ''X'' and a system Ω(''X'') of
open set In mathematics, an open set is a generalization of an Interval (mathematics)#Definitions_and_terminology, open interval in the real line. In a metric space (a Set (mathematics), set with a metric (mathematics), distance defined between every two ...
s of elements from ''X'', i.e. a subset of the
powerset In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of ''X''. It is known that Ω(''X'') has certain special properties: it is a
complete lattice In mathematics, a complete lattice is a partially ordered set in which all subsets have both a supremum ( join) and an infimum ( meet). A conditionally complete lattice satisfies at least one of these properties for bounded subsets. For compariso ...
within which suprema and finite
infima In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
are given by set unions and finite set intersections, respectively. Furthermore, it contains both ''X'' and the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
. Since the
embedding In mathematics, an embedding (or imbedding) is one instance of some mathematical structure contained within another instance, such as a group (mathematics), group that is a subgroup. When some object X is said to be embedded in another object Y ...
of Ω(''X'') into the powerset lattice of ''X'' preserves finite infima and arbitrary suprema, Ω(''X'') inherits the following distributivity law: :x \wedge \bigvee S = \bigvee \, for every element (open set) ''x'' and every subset ''S'' of Ω(''X''). Hence Ω(''X'') is not an arbitrary complete lattice but a ''complete Heyting algebra'' (also called ''frame'' or ''locale'' – the various names are primarily used to distinguish several categories that have the same class of objects but different morphisms: frame morphisms, locale morphisms and homomorphisms of complete Heyting algebras). Now an obvious question is: To what extent is a topological space characterized by its locale of open sets? As already hinted at above, one can go even further. The category Top of topological spaces has as morphisms the continuous functions, where a function ''f'' is continuous if the
inverse image In mathematics, for a function f: X \to Y, the image of an input value x is the single output value produced by f when passed x. The preimage of an output value y is the set of input values that produce y. More generally, evaluating f at each ...
''f'' −1(''O'') of any open set in the
codomain In mathematics, a codomain, counter-domain, or set of destination of a function is a set into which all of the output of the function is constrained to fall. It is the set in the notation . The term '' range'' is sometimes ambiguously used to ...
of ''f'' is open in the domain of ''f''. Thus any continuous function ''f'' from a space ''X'' to a space ''Y'' defines an inverse mapping ''f'' −1 from Ω(''Y'') to Ω(''X''). Furthermore, it is easy to check that ''f'' −1 (like any inverse image map) preserves finite intersections and arbitrary unions and therefore is a ''morphism of frames''. If we define Ω(''f'') = ''f'' −1 then Ω becomes a
contravariant functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a mapping between categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) are associated to topological spaces, and ...
from the category Top to the category Frm of frames and frame morphisms. Using the tools of category theory, the task of finding a characterization of topological spaces in terms of their open set lattices is equivalent to finding a functor from Frm to Top which is adjoint to Ω.


Points of a locale

The goal of this section is to define a functor pt from Frm to Top that in a certain sense "inverts" the operation of Ω by assigning to each locale ''L'' a set of points pt(''L'') (hence the notation pt) with a suitable topology. But how can we recover the set of points just from the locale, though it is not given as a lattice of sets? It is certain that one cannot expect in general that pt can reproduce all of the original elements of a topological space just from its lattice of open sets – for example all sets with the
indiscrete topology In topology, a topological space with the trivial topology is one where the only open sets are the empty set and the entire space. Such spaces are commonly called indiscrete, anti-discrete, concrete or codiscrete. Intuitively, this has the conseque ...
yield (up to isomorphism) the same locale, such that the information on the specific set is no longer present. However, there is still a reasonable technique for obtaining "points" from a locale, which indeed gives an example of a central construction for Stone-type duality theorems. Let us first look at the points of a topological space ''X''. One is usually tempted to consider a point of ''X'' as an element ''x'' of the set ''X'', but there is in fact a more useful description for our current investigation. Any point ''x'' gives rise to a continuous function ''p''''x'' from the one element topological space 1 (all subsets of which are open) to the space ''X'' by defining ''p''''x''(1) = ''x''. Conversely, any function from 1 to ''X'' clearly determines one point: the element that it "points" to. Therefore, the set of points of a topological space is equivalently characterized as the set of functions from 1 to ''X''. When using the functor Ω to pass from Top to Frm, all set-theoretic elements of a space are lost, but – using a fundamental idea of category theory – one can as well work on the
function space In mathematics, a function space is a set of functions between two fixed sets. Often, the domain and/or codomain will have additional structure which is inherited by the function space. For example, the set of functions from any set into a ve ...
s. Indeed, any "point" ''p''''x'': 1 → ''X'' in Top is mapped to a morphism Ω(''p''''x''): Ω(''X'') → Ω(1). The open set lattice of the one-element topological space Ω(1) is just (isomorphic to) the two-element locale 2 = with 0 < 1. After these observations it appears reasonable to define the set of points of a locale ''L'' to be the set of frame morphisms from ''L'' to 2. Yet, there is no guarantee that every point of the locale Ω(''X'') is in one-to-one correspondence to a point of the topological space ''X'' (consider again the indiscrete topology, for which the open set lattice has only one "point"). Before defining the required topology on pt(''X''), it is worthwhile to clarify the concept of a point of a locale further. The perspective motivated above suggests to consider a point of a locale ''L'' as a frame morphism ''p'' from ''L'' to 2. But these morphisms are characterized equivalently by the inverse images of the two elements of 2. From the properties of frame morphisms, one can derive that ''p'' −1(0) is a lower set (since ''p'' is monotone), which contains a greatest element ''a''''p'' = V ''p'' −1(0) (since ''p'' preserves arbitrary suprema). In addition, the
principal ideal In mathematics, specifically ring theory, a principal ideal is an ideal I in a ring R that is generated by a single element a of R through multiplication by every element of R. The term also has another, similar meaning in order theory, where ...
''p'' −1(0) is a
prime ideal In algebra, a prime ideal is a subset of a ring (mathematics), ring that shares many important properties of a prime number in the ring of Integer#Algebraic properties, integers. The prime ideals for the integers are the sets that contain all th ...
since ''p'' preserves finite infima and thus the principal ''a''''p'' is a meet-prime element. Now the set-inverse of ''p'' −1(0) given by ''p'' −1(1) is a completely prime filter because ''p'' −1(0) is a principal prime ideal. It turns out that all of these descriptions uniquely determine the initial frame morphism. We sum up: :A point of a locale ''L'' is equivalently described as: :* a frame morphism from ''L'' to 2 :* a principal prime ideal of ''L'' :* a meet-prime element of ''L'' :* a completely prime filter of ''L''. All of these descriptions have their place within the theory and it is convenient to switch between them as needed.


The functor pt

Now that a set of points is available for any locale, it remains to equip this set with an appropriate topology in order to define the object part of the functor pt. This is done by defining the open sets of pt(''L'') as :φ(''a'') = , for every element ''a'' of ''L''. Here we viewed the points of ''L'' as morphisms, but one can of course state a similar definition for all of the other equivalent characterizations. It can be shown that setting Ω(pt(''L'')) = does really yield a topological space (pt(''L''), Ω(pt(''L''))). It is common to abbreviate this space as pt(''L''). Finally pt can be defined on morphisms of Frm rather canonically by defining, for a frame morphism ''g'' from ''L'' to ''M'', pt(''g''): pt(''M'') → pt(''L'') as pt(''g'')(''p'') = ''p'' o ''g''. In words, we obtain a morphism from ''L'' to 2 (a point of ''L'') by applying the morphism ''g'' to get from ''L'' to ''M'' before applying the morphism ''p'' that maps from ''M'' to 2. Again, this can be formalized using the other descriptions of points of a locale as well – for example just calculate (''p'' o ''g'') −1(0).


The adjunction of Top and Loc

As noted several times before, pt and Ω usually are not inverses. In general neither is ''X''
homeomorphic In mathematics and more specifically in topology, a homeomorphism ( from Greek roots meaning "similar shape", named by Henri Poincaré), also called topological isomorphism, or bicontinuous function, is a bijective and continuous function betw ...
to pt(Ω(''X'')) nor is ''L'' order-isomorphic to Ω(pt(''L'')). However, when introducing the topology of pt(''L'') above, a mapping φ from ''L'' to Ω(pt(''L'')) was applied. This mapping is indeed a frame morphism. Conversely, we can define a continuous function ψ from ''X'' to pt(Ω(''X'')) by setting ψ(''x'') = Ω(''p''''x''), where ''p''''x'' is just the characteristic function for the point ''x'' from 1 to ''X'' as described above. Another convenient description is given by viewing points of a locale as meet-prime elements. In this case we have ψ(''x'') = ''X'' \ Cl, where Cl denotes the topological closure of the set and \ is just set-difference. At this point we already have more than enough data to obtain the desired result: the functors Ω and pt define an adjunction between the categories Top and Loc = Frmop, where pt is right adjoint to Ω and the
natural transformation In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a natural transformation provides a way of transforming one functor into another while respecting the internal structure (i.e., the composition of morphisms) of the categories involved. Hence, a natur ...
s ψ and φop provide the required unit and counit, respectively.


The duality theorem

The above adjunction is not an equivalence of the categories Top and Loc (or, equivalently, a duality of Top and Frm). For this it is necessary that both ψ and φ are isomorphisms in their respective categories. For a space ''X'', ψ: ''X'' → pt(Ω(''X'')) is a homeomorphism
if and only if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
it is
bijective In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
. Using the characterization via meet-prime elements of the open set lattice, one sees that this is the case if and only if every meet-prime open set is of the form ''X'' \ Cl for a unique ''x''. Alternatively, every join-prime closed set is the closure of a unique point, where "join-prime" can be replaced by (join-) irreducible since we are in a distributive lattice. Spaces with this property are called sober. Conversely, for a locale ''L'', φ: ''L'' → Ω(pt(''L'')) is always surjective. It is additionally injective if and only if any two elements ''a'' and ''b'' of ''L'' for which ''a'' is not less-or-equal to ''b'' can be separated by points of the locale, formally: : if not ''a'' ≤ ''b'', then there is a point ''p'' in pt(''L'') such that p(''a'') = 1 and p(''b'') = 0. If this condition is satisfied for all elements of the locale, then the locale is spatial, or said to have enough points. (See also well-pointed category for a similar condition in more general categories.) Finally, one can verify that for every space ''X'', Ω(''X'') is spatial and for every locale ''L'', pt(''L'') is sober. Hence, it follows that the above adjunction of Top and Loc restricts to an equivalence of the full subcategories Sob of sober spaces and SLoc of spatial locales. This main result is completed by the observation that for the functor pt o Ω, sending each space to the points of its open set lattice is left adjoint to the
inclusion functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a subcategory of a category ''C'' is a category ''S'' whose objects are objects in ''C'' and whose morphisms are morphisms in ''C'' with the same identities and composition of morphisms. Intuitively, ...
from Sob to Top. For a space ''X'', pt(Ω(''X'')) is called its soberification. The case of the functor Ω o pt is symmetric but a special name for this operation is not commonly used.


References

* Stanley N. Burris and H. P. Sankappanavar, 1981.
A Course in Universal Algebra.
'
Springer-Verlag Springer Science+Business Media, commonly known as Springer, is a German multinational publishing company of books, e-books and peer-reviewed journals in science, humanities, technical and medical (STM) publishing. Originally founded in 1842 in ...
. . (available free online at the website mentioned) * P. T. Johnstone, ''Stone Spaces'', Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics 3,
Cambridge University Press Cambridge University Press was the university press of the University of Cambridge. Granted a letters patent by King Henry VIII in 1534, it was the oldest university press in the world. Cambridge University Press merged with Cambridge Assessme ...
, Cambridge, 1982. . * *
Abstract Stone Duality
* {{cite arXiv, authorlink1=Olivia Caramello , last=Caramello , first=Olivia , title=A topos-theoretic approach to Stone-type dualities , year=2011 , class=math.CT , eprint=1103.3493 Topology Order theory Duality theories