Proof that e is irrational
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The number ''e'' was introduced by
Jacob Bernoulli Jacob Bernoulli (also known as James or Jacques; – 16 August 1705) was one of the many prominent mathematicians in the Bernoulli family. He was an early proponent of Leibnizian calculus and sided with Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz during the Le ...
in 1683. More than half a century later, Euler, who had been a student of Jacob's younger brother
Johann Johann, typically a male given name, is the German form of ''Iohannes'', which is the Latin form of the Greek name ''Iōánnēs'' (), itself derived from Hebrew name '' Yochanan'' () in turn from its extended form (), meaning "Yahweh is Gracious ...
, proved that ''e'' is
irrational Irrationality is cognition, thinking, talking, or acting without inclusion of rationality. It is more specifically described as an action or opinion given through inadequate use of reason, or through emotional distress or cognitive deficiency. T ...
; that is, that it cannot be expressed as the quotient of two integers.


Euler's proof

Euler wrote the first proof of the fact that ''e'' is irrational in 1737 (but the text was only published seven years later). He computed the representation of ''e'' as a
simple continued fraction In mathematics, a continued fraction is an expression obtained through an iterative process of representing a number as the sum of its integer part and the reciprocal of another number, then writing this other number as the sum of its integer pa ...
, which is :e = ; 1, 2, 1, 1, 4, 1, 1, 6, 1, 1, 8, 1, 1, \ldots, 2n, 1, 1, \ldots Since this continued fraction is infinite and every rational number has a terminating continued fraction, ''e'' is irrational. A short proof of the previous equality is known. Since the simple continued fraction of ''e'' is not periodic, this also proves that ''e'' is not a root of a quadratic polynomial with rational coefficients; in particular, ''e''2 is irrational.


Fourier's proof

The most well-known proof is Joseph Fourier's
proof by contradiction In logic and mathematics, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition, by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction. Proof by contradiction is also known ...
, which is based upon the equality : e = \sum_^\infty \frac. Initially ''e'' is assumed to be a rational number of the form . The idea is to then analyze the scaled-up difference (here denoted ''x'') between the series representation of ''e'' and its strictly smaller partial sum, which approximates the limiting value ''e''. By choosing the scale factor to be the factorial of ''b'', the fraction and the partial sum are turned into
integer An integer is the number zero (), a positive natural number (, , , etc.) or a negative integer with a minus sign ( −1, −2, −3, etc.). The negative numbers are the additive inverses of the corresponding positive numbers. In the languag ...
s, hence ''x'' must be a positive integer. However, the fast convergence of the series representation implies that ''x'' is still strictly smaller than 1. From this contradiction we deduce that ''e'' is irrational. Now for the details. If ''e'' is a
rational number In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (e.g. ). The set of all rat ...
, there exist positive integers ''a'' and ''b'' such that . Define the number : x = b!\left(e - \sum_^ \frac\right). Use the assumption that ''e'' = to obtain : x = b!\left (\frac - \sum_^ \frac\right) = a(b - 1)! - \sum_^ \frac. The first term is an integer, and every fraction in the sum is actually an integer because for each term. Therefore, under the assumption that ''e'' is rational, ''x'' is an integer. We now prove that . First, to prove that ''x'' is strictly positive, we insert the above series representation of ''e'' into the definition of ''x'' and obtain : x = b!\left(\sum_^ \frac - \sum_^ \frac\right) = \sum_^ \frac>0, because all the terms are strictly positive. We now prove that . For all terms with we have the upper estimate : \frac =\frac1 \le \frac1. This inequality is strict for every . Changing the index of summation to and using the formula for the
infinite geometric series In mathematics, a geometric series is the sum of an infinite number of terms that have a constant ratio between successive terms. For example, the series :\frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \cdots is geometric, because each suc ...
, we obtain :x =\sum_^\infty \frac < \sum_^\infty \frac1 =\sum_^\infty \frac1 =\frac \left (\frac1\right) = \frac \le 1. Since there is no integer strictly between 0 and 1, we have reached a contradiction, and so ''e'' is irrational, Q.E.D.


Alternate proofs

Another proof can be obtained from the previous one by noting that : (b + 1)x = 1 + \frac1 + \frac1 + \cdots < 1 + \frac1 + \frac1 + \cdots = 1 + x, and this inequality is equivalent to the assertion that ''bx'' < 1. This is impossible, of course, since ''b'' and ''x'' are positive integers. Still another proof can be obtained from the fact that : \frac = e^ = \sum_^\infty \frac. Define s_n as follows: : s_n = \sum_^n \frac. Then : e^ - s_ = \sum_^\infty \frac - \sum_^ \frac < \frac, which implies : 0 < (2n - 1)! \left(e^ - s_\right) < \frac \le \frac for any positive integer n. Note that (2n - 1)!s_ is always an integer. Assume that e^ is rational, so e^ = p/q, where p, q are co-prime, and q \neq 0. It is possible to appropriately choose n so that (2n - 1)!e^ is an integer, i.e. n \geq (q + 1)/2. Hence, for this choice, the difference between (2n - 1)!e^ and (2n - 1)!s_ would be an integer. But from the above inequality, that is not possible. So, e^ is irrational. This means that e is irrational.


Generalizations

In 1840,
Liouville Joseph Liouville (; ; 24 March 1809 – 8 September 1882) was a French mathematician and engineer. Life and work He was born in Saint-Omer in France on 24 March 1809. His parents were Claude-Joseph Liouville (an army officer) and Thérèse ...
published a proof of the fact that ''e''2 is irrational followed by a proof that ''e''2 is not a root of a second-degree polynomial with rational coefficients. This last fact implies that ''e''4 is irrational. His proofs are similar to Fourier's proof of the irrationality of ''e''. In 1891,
Hurwitz Hurwitz is one of the variants of a surname of Ashkenazi Jewish origin (for historical background see the Horowitz page). Notable people with the surname include: *Adolf Hurwitz (1859–1919), German mathematician ** Hurwitz polynomial **Hurwitz m ...
explained how it is possible to prove along the same line of ideas that ''e'' is not a root of a third-degree polynomial with rational coefficients, which implies that ''e''3 is irrational. More generally, ''e''''q'' is irrational for any non-zero rational ''q''.
Charles Hermite Charles Hermite () FRS FRSE MIAS (24 December 1822 – 14 January 1901) was a French mathematician who did research concerning number theory, quadratic forms, invariant theory, orthogonal polynomials, elliptic functions, and algebra. Hermi ...
further proved that ''e'' is a
transcendental number In mathematics, a transcendental number is a number that is not algebraic—that is, not the root of a non-zero polynomial of finite degree with rational coefficients. The best known transcendental numbers are and . Though only a few classes ...
, in 1873, which means that is not a root of any polynomial with rational coefficients, as is for any non-zero algebraic ''α''.{{cite journal , last=Hermite , first=C. , author-link=Charles Hermite , year=1873 , title=Sur la fonction exponentielle , lang=fr , journal=Comptes rendus de l'Académie des Sciences de Paris , volume=77 , pages=18–24


See also

*
Characterizations of the exponential function In mathematics, the exponential function can be characterized in many ways. The following characterizations (definitions) are most common. This article discusses why each characterization makes sense, and why the characterizations are independent o ...
*
Transcendental number In mathematics, a transcendental number is a number that is not algebraic—that is, not the root of a non-zero polynomial of finite degree with rational coefficients. The best known transcendental numbers are and . Though only a few classes ...
, including a proof that ''e'' is transcendental *
Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem In transcendental number theory, the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem is a result that is very useful in establishing the transcendence of numbers. It states the following: In other words, the extension field \mathbb(e^, \dots, e^) has transce ...
*
Proof that π is irrational In the 1760s, Johann Heinrich Lambert was the first to prove that the number is irrational, meaning it cannot be expressed as a fraction a/b, where a and b are both integers. In the 19th century, Charles Hermite found a proof that requires no p ...


References

Diophantine approximation Exponentials Article proofs E (mathematical constant) Irrational numbers