HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The participation criterion is a
voting system criterion Electoral systems are the rules for conducting elections, a main component of which is the algorithm for determining the winner (or several winners) from the ballots cast. This article discusses methods and results of comparing different electora ...
. Voting systems that fail the participation criterion are said to exhibit the no show paradox and allow a particularly unusual strategy of
tactical voting Strategic voting, also called tactical voting, sophisticated voting or insincere voting, occurs in voting systems when a voter votes for another candidate or party than their ''sincere preference'' to prevent an undesirable outcome. For example, ...
: abstaining from an election can help a voter's preferred choice win. The criterion has been defined as follows: * In a deterministic framework, the participation criterion says that the addition of a ballot, where candidate A is strictly preferred to candidate B, to an existing tally of votes should not change the winner from candidate A to candidate B. * In a probabilistic framework, the participation criterion says that the addition of a ballot, where each candidate of the set X is strictly preferred to each other candidate, to an existing tally of votes should not reduce the probability that the winner is chosen from the set X.
Plurality voting Plurality voting refers to electoral systems in which a candidate, or candidates, who poll more than any other counterpart (that is, receive a plurality), are elected. In systems based on single-member districts, it elects just one member per ...
,
approval voting Approval voting is an electoral system in which voters can select many candidates instead of selecting only one candidate. Description Approval voting ballots show a list of the options of candidates running. Approval voting lets each voter i ...
,
range voting Score voting or range voting is an electoral system for single-seat elections, in which voters give each candidate a score, the scores are added (or averaged), and the candidate with the highest total is elected. It has been described by various ...
, and the
Borda count The Borda count is a family of positional voting rules which gives each candidate, for each ballot, a number of points corresponding to the number of candidates ranked lower. In the original variant, the lowest-ranked candidate gets 0 points, the ...
all satisfy the participation criterion. All
Condorcet method A Condorcet method (; ) is an election method that elects the candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates, that is, a candidate preferred by more voters than any others, whenever ...
s,
Bucklin voting Bucklin voting is a class of voting methods that can be used for single-member and multi-member districts. As in highest median rules like the majority judgment, the Bucklin winner will be one of the candidates with the highest median ranking ...
, and IRV fail. The participation criterion for voting systems is one example of a rational participation constraint for
social choice Social choice theory or social choice is a theoretical framework for analysis of combining individual opinions, preferences, interests, or welfares to reach a ''collective decision'' or ''social welfare'' in some sense.Amartya Sen (2008). "Soci ...
mechanisms in general.


Quorum requirements

The most common failure of the participation criterion is not in the use of particular voting systems, but in simple yes or no measures that place
quorum A quorum is the minimum number of members of a deliberative assembly (a body that uses parliamentary procedure, such as a legislature) necessary to conduct the business of that group. According to '' Robert's Rules of Order Newly Revised'', the ...
requirements. A public
referendum A referendum (plural: referendums or less commonly referenda) is a Direct democracy, direct vote by the Constituency, electorate on a proposal, law, or political issue. This is in contrast to an issue being voted on by a Representative democr ...
, for example, if it required majority approval and a certain number of voters to participate in order to pass, would fail the participation criterion, as a minority of voters preferring the "no" option could cause the measure to fail by simply not voting rather than voting no. In other words, the addition of a "no" vote may make the measure more likely to pass. A referendum that required a minimum number of yes votes (not counting no votes), by contrast, would pass the participation criterion.


Incompatibility with the Condorcet criterion

Hervé Moulin Hervé Moulin (born 1950 in Paris) is a French mathematician who is the Donald J. Robertson Chair of Economics at the Adam Smith Business School at the University of Glasgow. He is known for his research contributions in mathematical economics, ...
showed in 1988 that whenever there are at least four candidates and at least 25 voters, no resolute (single-valued) Condorcet consistent voting rule satisfies the participation criterion. However, when there are at most three candidates, the minimax method (with some fixed tie-breaking) satisfies both the Condorcet and the participation criterion. Similarly, when there are four candidates and at most 11 voters, there is a voting rule that satisfies both criteria, but no such rule exists for four candidates and 12 voters. Similar incompatibilities have also been proven for set-valued voting rules. Certain conditions that are weaker than the participation criterion are also incompatible with the Condorcet criterion. For example, ''weak positive involvement'' requires that adding a ballot in which candidate A is ''most''-preferred does not change the winner away from A; similarly, weak ''negative'' involvement requires that adding a ballot in which A is ''least''-preferred does not make A the winner if it was not the winner before. Both conditions are incompatible with the Condorcet criterion if one allows ballots to include ties. Another condition that is weaker than participation is ''half-way monotonicity'', which requires that a voter cannot be better off by completely reversing their ballot. Again, half-way monotonicity is incompatible with the Condorcet criterion.


Examples


Copeland

This example shows that Copeland's method violates the participation criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D with 13 potential voters and the following preferences: The three voters with preferences A > B > C > D are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the 3 voters would not show up at the polling place. The preferences of the remaining 10 voters would be: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: A can defeat two of the three opponents, whereas no other candidate wins against more than one opponent. Thus, A is elected Copeland winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the three unconfident voters decide to participate: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: B is the Condorcet winner and thus, B is Copeland winner, too.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the three voters supporting A would change A from winner to loser. Their first preferences were not sufficient to change the one pairwise defeat A suffers without their support. But, their second preferences for B turned both defeats B would have suffered into wins and made B Condorcet winner and thus, overcoming A. Hence, Copeland fails the participation criterion.


Instant-runoff voting

This example shows that instant-runoff voting violates the participation criterion. Assume three candidates A, B and C and 15 potential voters, two of them (in blue) unconfident whether to vote.


Voters not participating

If they don't show up at the election the remaining voters would be: The following outcome results: Result: After A is eliminated first, B gets their votes and wins.


Voters participating

If they participate in the election, the preferences list is: The outcome changes as follows: Result: Now, B is eliminated first and C gets their votes and wins.


Conclusion

The additional votes for A were not sufficient for winning, but for descending to the second round, thereby eliminating the second preference of the voters. Thus, due to participating in the election, the voters changed the winner from their second preference to their strictly least preference. Thus, instant-runoff voting fails the participation criterion.


Kemeny–Young method

This example shows that the Kemeny–Young method violates the participation criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C, D with 21 voters and the following preferences: The three voters with preferences A > B > C > D are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the 3 voters would not show up at the polling place. The preferences of the remaining 18 voters would be: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: Result: The ranking A > D > C > B has the highest ranking score of 67 (= 13 + 13 + 13 + 12 + 9 + 7); against e.g. 65 (= 13 + 13 + 13 + 11 + 9 + 6) of B > A > D > C. Thus, A is Kemeny-Young winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the 3 unconfident voters decide to participate: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: Result: The ranking B > A > D > C has the highest ranking score of 77 (= 16 + 16 + 13 + 12 + 11 + 9); against e.g. 76 (= 16 + 16 + 13 + 12 + 10 + 9) of A > D > C > B. Thus, B is Kemeny-Young winner.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the three voters supporting A would change A from winner to loser. Their ballots support 3 of the 6 pairwise comparisons of the ranking A > D > C >B, but four pairwise comparisons of the ranking B > A > D > C, enough to overcome the first one. Thus, Kemeny-Young fails the participation criterion.


Majority judgment

This example shows that majority judgment violates the participation criterion. Assume two candidates A and B with 5 potential voters and the following ratings: The two voters rating A "Excellent" are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the 2 voters would not show up at the polling place. The ratings of the remaining 3 voters would be: The sorted ratings would be as follows: Result: A has the median rating of "Fair" and B has the median rating of "Poor". Thus, A is elected majority judgment winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the 2 unconfident voters decide to participate: The sorted ratings would be as follows: Result: A has the median rating of "Fair" and B has the median rating of "Good". Thus, B is the majority judgment winner.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the two voters preferring A would change A from winner to loser. Their "Excellent" rating for A was not sufficient to change A's median rating since no other voter rated A higher than "Fair". But, their "Good" rating for B turned B's median rating to "Good", since another voter agreed with this rating. Thus, majority judgment fails the participation criterion.


Minimax

This example shows that the minimax method violates the participation criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C, D with 18 potential voters and the following preferences: Since all preferences are strict rankings (no equals are present), all three minimax methods (winning votes, margins and pairwise opposite) elect the same winners. The two voters (in blue) with preferences A > B > C > D are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the two voters would not show up at the polling place. The preferences of the remaining 16 voters would be: The results would be tabulated as follows: * indicates voters who preferred the candidate listed in the column caption to the candidate listed in the row caption * indicates voters who preferred the candidate listed in the row caption to the candidate listed in the column caption Result: B has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, B is elected minimax winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the two unconfident voters decide to participate: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: C has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, C is elected minimax winner.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the two voters changed the winner from B to C whilst strictly preferring B to C. Their preferences of B over C and D does not advance B's minimax value since B's biggest defeat was against A. Also, their preferences of A and B over C does not degrade C's minimax value since C's biggest defeat was against D. Therefore, only the comparison "A > B" degrade B's value and the comparison "C > D" advanced C's value. This results in C overcoming B. Thus, the minimax method fails the participation criterion.


Ranked pairs

This example shows that the ranked pairs method violates the participation criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D with 26 potential voters and the following preferences: The four voters with preferences A > B > C > D are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the 4 voters do not show up at the polling place. The preferences of the remaining 22 voters would be: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: A > D, B > C and D > B are locked in (and the other three can't be locked in after that), so the full ranking is A > D > B > C. Thus, A is elected ranked pairs winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the 4 unconfident voters decide to participate: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: A > D, B > C and C > D are locked in first. Now, D > B can't be locked in since it would create a cycle B > C > D > B. Finally, B > A and C > A are locked in. Hence, the full ranking is B > C > A > D. Thus, B is elected ranked pairs winner.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the four voters supporting A would change A from winner to loser. The clear victory of D > B was essential for A's win in the first place. The additional votes diminished that victory and at the same time gave a boost to the victory of C > D, turning D > B into the weakest link of the cycle B > C > D > B. Since A had no other victories but the one over D and B had no other losses but the one over D, the elimination of D > B made it impossible for A to win. Thus, the ranked pairs method fails the participation criterion.


Schulze method

This example shows that the Schulze method violates the participation criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D with 25 potential voters and the following preferences: The two voters with preferences A > B > C > D are unconfident whether to participate in the election.


Voters not participating

Assume the two voters would not show up at the polling place. The preferences of the remaining 23 voters would be: The pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified, e.g. the path A > D > B is stronger than the direct path A > B (which is nullified, since it is a loss for A). Result: The full ranking is A > D > C > B. Thus, A is elected Schulze winner.


Voters participating

Now, consider the 2 unconfident voters decide to participate: The pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified, e.g. the path C > A > D is stronger than the direct path C > D. Result: The full ranking is B > A > D > C. Thus, B is elected Schulze winner.


Conclusion

By participating in the election the two voters supporting A changed the winner from A to B. In fact, the voters can turn the defeat in direct pairwise comparison of A against B into a victory. But in this example, the relation between A and B does not depend on the direct comparison, since the paths A > D > B and B > C > A are stronger. The additional voters diminish D > B, the weakest link of the A > D > B path, while giving a boost to B > C, the weakest link of the path B > C > A. Thus, the Schulze method fails the participation criterion.


See also

*
Consistency criterion A voting system is consistent if, whenever the electorate is divided (arbitrarily) into several parts and elections in those parts garner the same result, then an election of the entire electorate also garners that result. Smith calls this property ...
*
Voting system An electoral system or voting system is a set of rules that determine how elections and referendums are conducted and how their results are determined. Electoral systems are used in politics to elect governments, while non-political elections m ...


References


Further reading

* Woodall, Douglas R,
Monotonicity and Single-Seat Election Rules
''Voting matters'', Issue 6, 1996 {{voting systems Electoral system criteria Mechanism design