HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

A
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwee ...
of the predicate calculus is in prenex normal form (PNF) if it is written as a string of quantifiers and
bound variables In mathematics, and in other disciplines involving formal languages, including mathematical logic and computer science, a free variable is a notation (symbol) that specifies places in an expression where substitution may take place and is not ...
, called the prefix, followed by a quantifier-free part, called the matrix. Together with the normal forms in propositional logic (e.g. disjunctive normal form or conjunctive normal form), it provides a
canonical normal form In Boolean algebra, any Boolean function can be expressed in the canonical disjunctive normal form ( CDNF) or minterm canonical form and its dual canonical conjunctive normal form ( CCNF) or maxterm canonical form. Other canonical forms include ...
useful in
automated theorem proving Automated theorem proving (also known as ATP or automated deduction) is a subfield of automated reasoning and mathematical logic dealing with proving mathematical theorems by computer programs. Automated reasoning over mathematical proof was a maj ...
. Every formula in
classical logic Classical logic (or standard logic or Frege-Russell logic) is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy. Characteristics Each logical system in this class ...
is equivalent to a formula in prenex normal form. For example, if \phi(y), \psi(z), and \rho(x) are quantifier-free formulas with the free variables shown then :\forall x \exists y \forall z (\phi(y) \lor (\psi(z) \rightarrow \rho(x))) is in prenex normal form with matrix \phi(y) \lor (\psi(z) \rightarrow \rho(x)), while :\forall x ((\exists y \phi(y)) \lor ((\exists z \psi(z) ) \rightarrow \rho(x))) is logically equivalent but not in prenex normal form.


Conversion to prenex form

Every
first-order In mathematics and other formal sciences, first-order or first order most often means either: * "linear" (a polynomial of degree at most one), as in first-order approximation and other calculus uses, where it is contrasted with "polynomials of high ...
formula is logically equivalent (in classical logic) to some formula in prenex normal form.Hinman, P. (2005), p. 111 There are several conversion rules that can be recursively applied to convert a formula to prenex normal form. The rules depend on which
logical connective In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. They can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the binary co ...
s appear in the formula.


Conjunction and disjunction

The rules for conjunction and
disjunction In logic, disjunction is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is raining or it is snowing" can be represented in logic using the disjunctive formula R \lor S ...
say that :(\forall x \phi) \land \psi is equivalent to \forall x ( \phi \land \psi) under (mild) additional condition \exists x \top, or, equivalently, \lnot\forall x \bot (meaning that at least one individual exists), :(\forall x \phi) \lor \psi is equivalent to \forall x ( \phi \lor \psi); and :(\exists x \phi) \land \psi is equivalent to \exists x (\phi \land \psi), :(\exists x \phi) \lor \psi is equivalent to \exists x (\phi \lor \psi) under additional condition \exists x \top. The equivalences are valid when x does not appear as a free variable of \psi; if x does appear free in \psi, one can rename the bound x in (\exists x \phi) and obtain the equivalent (\exists x' \phi /x'. For example, in the language of rings, :(\exists x (x^2 = 1)) \land (0 = y) is equivalent to \exists x ( x^2 = 1 \land 0 = y), but :(\exists x (x^2 = 1)) \land (0 = x) is not equivalent to \exists x ( x^2 = 1 \land 0 = x) because the formula on the left is true in any ring when the free variable ''x'' is equal to 0, while the formula on the right has no free variables and is false in any nontrivial ring. So (\exists x (x^2 = 1)) \land (0 = x) will be first rewritten as (\exists x' (x'^2 = 1)) \land (0 = x) and then put in prenex normal form \exists x' ( x'^2 = 1 \land 0 = x).


Negation

The rules for negation say that :\lnot \exists x \phi is equivalent to \forall x \lnot \phi and :\lnot \forall x \phi is equivalent to \exists x \lnot \phi.


Implication

There are four rules for implication: two that remove quantifiers from the antecedent and two that remove quantifiers from the consequent. These rules can be derived by
rewriting In mathematics, computer science, and logic, rewriting covers a wide range of methods of replacing subterms of a well-formed formula, formula with other terms. Such methods may be achieved by rewriting systems (also known as rewrite systems, rewr ...
the implication \phi \rightarrow \psi as \lnot \phi \lor \psi and applying the rules for disjunction above. As with the rules for disjunction, these rules require that the variable quantified in one subformula does not appear free in the other subformula. The rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent are (note the change of quantifiers): :(\forall x \phi ) \rightarrow \psi is equivalent to \exists x (\phi \rightarrow \psi) (under the assumption that \exists x \top), :(\exists x \phi ) \rightarrow \psi is equivalent to \forall x (\phi \rightarrow \psi). The rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are: :\phi \rightarrow (\exists x \psi) is equivalent to \exists x (\phi \rightarrow \psi) (under the assumption that \exists x \top), :\phi \rightarrow (\forall x \psi) is equivalent to \forall x (\phi \rightarrow \psi). For example, when the
range of quantification In logic, a quantifier is an operator that specifies how many individuals in the domain of discourse satisfy an open formula. For instance, the universal quantifier \forall in the first order formula \forall x P(x) expresses that everythin ...
is the non-negative
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called ''Cardinal n ...
(viz. n\in \mathbb), the statement : forall n\in \mathbb (x< n) \rightarrow (x< 0) is logically equivalent to the statement :\exists n\in \mathbb (x< n) \rightarrow (x< 0)/math> The former statement says that if ''x'' is less than any natural number, then ''x'' is less than zero; The latter statement says that there exists some natural number ''n'' such that if ''x'' is less than ''n'', then ''x'' is less than zero. Both statements are true. The former statement is true because if ''x'' is less than any natural number, it must be less than the smallest natural number (zero); The latter is true because ''n=0'' makes the implication a tautology. Note that the placement of brackets implies the scope of the quantification, which is very important for the meaning of the formula. Consider the following two statements: :\forall n\in \mathbb x< n) \rightarrow (x< 0)/math> and its logically equivalent statement : exists n\in \mathbb (x< n) \rightarrow (x< 0) The former statement says that for any natural number ''n'', if ''x'' is less than ''n'' then ''x'' is less than zero; The latter statement says that if there exists some natural number ''n'' such that ''x'' is less than ''n'', then ''x'' is less than zero. Both statements are false. The former statement doesn't hold for ''n=2'', because ''x=1'' is less than ''n'', but not less than zero; The latter doesn't hold for ''x=1'', because the natural number ''n=2'' satisfies ''x

Example

Suppose that \phi, \psi, and \rho are quantifier-free formulas and no two of these formulas share any free variable. Consider the formula : (\phi \lor \exists x \psi) \rightarrow \forall z \rho. By recursively applying the rules starting at the innermost subformulas, the following sequence of logically equivalent formulas can be obtained: : (\phi \lor \exists x \psi) \rightarrow \forall z \rho. : ( \exists x (\phi \lor \psi) ) \rightarrow \forall z \rho, : \neg( \exists x (\phi \lor \psi) ) \lor \forall z \rho, : (\forall x \neg(\phi \lor \psi)) \lor \forall z \rho, : \forall x (\neg(\phi \lor \psi) \lor \forall z \rho), : \forall x ( ( \phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \forall z \rho ), : \forall x ( \forall z (( \phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \rho )), : \forall x \forall z ( ( \phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \rho ). This is not the only prenex form equivalent to the original formula. For example, by dealing with the consequent before the antecedent in the example above, the prenex form :\forall z \forall x ( ( \phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \rho) can be obtained: : \forall z ( (\phi \lor \exists x \psi) \rightarrow \rho ) : \forall z ( (\exists x (\phi \lor \psi) ) \rightarrow \rho ), : \forall z ( \forall x ( (\phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \rho ) ), : \forall z \forall x ( (\phi \lor \psi) \rightarrow \rho ). The
ordering Order, ORDER or Orders may refer to: * Categorization, the process in which ideas and objects are recognized, differentiated, and understood * Heterarchy, a system of organization wherein the elements have the potential to be ranked a number of d ...
of the two universal quantifier with the same scope doesn't change the meaning/truth value of the statement.


Intuitionistic logic

The rules for converting a formula to prenex form make heavy use of classical logic. In intuitionistic logic, it is not true that every formula is logically equivalent to a prenex formula. The negation connective is one obstacle, but not the only one. The implication operator is also treated differently in intuitionistic logic than classical logic; in intuitionistic logic, it is not definable using disjunction and negation. The
BHK interpretation BHK is a three-letter abbreviation that may refer to: * BHK interpretation of intuitionistic predicate logic * Baby hamster kidney cells used in molecular biology * Bachelor of Human Kinetics (BHk) degree. * Baltische Historische Kommission, organi ...
illustrates why some formulas have no intuitionistically-equivalent prenex form. In this interpretation, a proof of :(\exists x \phi) \rightarrow \exists y \psi \qquad (1) is a function which, given a concrete ''x'' and a proof of \phi (x), produces a concrete ''y'' and a proof of \psi (y). In this case it is allowable for the value of ''y'' to be computed from the given value of ''x''. A proof of :\exists y ( \exists x \phi \rightarrow \psi), \qquad (2) on the other hand, produces a single concrete value of ''y'' and a function that converts any proof of \exists x \phi into a proof of \psi (y). If each ''x'' satisfying \phi can be used to construct a ''y'' satisfying \psi but no such ''y'' can be constructed without knowledge of such an ''x'' then formula (1) will not be equivalent to formula (2). The rules for converting a formula to prenex form that do ''fail'' in intuitionistic logic are: :(1) \forall x (\phi \lor \psi) implies (\forall x \phi) \lor \psi, :(2) \forall x (\phi \lor \psi) implies \phi \lor (\forall x \psi), :(3) (\forall x \phi) \rightarrow \psi implies \exists x (\phi \rightarrow \psi), :(4) \phi \rightarrow (\exists x \psi) implies \exists x (\phi \rightarrow \psi), :(5) \lnot \forall x \phi implies \exists x \lnot \phi, (''x'' does not appear as a free variable of \,\psi in (1) and (3); ''x'' does not appear as a free variable of \,\phi in (2) and (4)).


Use of prenex form

Some
proof calculi In mathematical logic, a proof calculus or a proof system is built to prove statements. Overview A proof system includes the components: * Language: The set ''L'' of formulas admitted by the system, for example, propositional logic or first-order ...
will only deal with a theory whose formulae are written in prenex normal form. The concept is essential for developing the arithmetical hierarchy and the analytical hierarchy. Gödel's proof of his
completeness theorem Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
for first-order logic presupposes that all formulae have been recast in prenex normal form.
Tarski's axioms Tarski's axioms, due to Alfred Tarski, are an axiom set for the substantial fragment of Euclidean geometry that is formulable in first-order logic with identity, and requiring no set theory (i.e., that part of Euclidean geometry that is formulabl ...
for geometry is a logical system whose sentences can ''all'' be written in universal-existential form, a special case of the prenex normal form that has every
universal quantifier In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
preceding any existential quantifier, so that all sentences can be rewritten in the form \forall u \forall v \ldots \exists a \exists b \phi, where \phi is a sentence that does not contain any quantifier. This fact allowed Tarski to prove that Euclidean geometry is decidable.


See also

* Arithmetical hierarchy * Herbrandization * Skolemization


Notes


References

* * * * {{Citation , last1=Hinman , first1=P. , title=Fundamentals of Mathematical Logic , publisher= A K Peters , isbn=978-1-56881-262-5 , year=2005 Normal forms (logic)