Preference Representation Theorem
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
economics Economics () is a behavioral science that studies the Production (economics), production, distribution (economics), distribution, and Consumption (economics), consumption of goods and services. Economics focuses on the behaviour and interac ...
, a utility representation theorem shows that, under certain conditions, a preference ordering can be represented by a real-valued
utility function In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings. * In a Normative economics, normative context, utility refers to a goal or ob ...
, such that option A is preferred to option B if and only if the utility of A is larger than that of B. The most famous example of a utility representation theorem is the
Von Neumann–Morgenstern utility theorem In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem demonstrates that rational choice under uncertainty involves making decisions that take the form of maximizing the expected value of some cardinal utility function. The theo ...
, which shows that any
rational agent A rational agent or rational being is a person or entity that always aims to perform optimal actions based on given premises and information. A rational agent can be anything that makes decisions, typically a person, firm, machine, or software. ...
has a utility function that measures their preferences over
lotteries A lottery (or lotto) is a form of gambling that involves the drawing of numbers at random for a prize. Some governments outlaw lotteries, while others endorse it to the extent of organizing a national or state lottery. It is common to find som ...
.


Background

Suppose a person is asked questions of the form "Do you prefer A or B?" (when A and B can be options, actions to take, states of the world, consumption bundles, etc.). If the agent prefers A to B, we write A\succ B. The set of all such preference-pairs forms the person's '' preference relation.'' Instead of recording the person's preferences between every pair of options, it would be much more convenient to have a single ''
utility function In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings. * In a Normative economics, normative context, utility refers to a goal or ob ...
'' - a function ''u'' that assigns a real number to each option, such that u(A)>u(B) if and only if A\succ B. Not every preference-relation has a utility-function representation. For example, if the relation is not transitive (the agent prefers A to B, B to C, and C to A), then it has no utility representation, since any such utility function would have to satisfy u(A)>u(B) > u(C) > u(A), which is impossible. A utility representation theorem gives conditions on a preference relation, that are sufficient for the existence of a utility representation. Often, one would like the representing function ''u'' to satisfy additional conditions, such as continuity. This requires additional conditions on the preference relation.


Definitions

The set of options is a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
denoted by ''X''. In some cases we assume that ''X'' is also a
metric space In mathematics, a metric space is a Set (mathematics), set together with a notion of ''distance'' between its Element (mathematics), elements, usually called point (geometry), points. The distance is measured by a function (mathematics), functi ...
; in particular, ''X'' can be a subset of a
Euclidean space Euclidean space is the fundamental space of geometry, intended to represent physical space. Originally, in Euclid's ''Elements'', it was the three-dimensional space of Euclidean geometry, but in modern mathematics there are ''Euclidean spaces ...
''Rm'', such that each coordinate in represents a commodity, and each ''m''-vector in ''X'' represents a possible consumption bundle.


Preference relations

A ''preference relation'' is a subset of X\times X. It is denoted by either \succ or \succeq: * The notation \succ is used when the relation is ''strict'', that is, A\succ B means that option A is strictly better than option B. In this case, the relation should be
irreflexive In mathematics, a binary relation R on a set X is reflexive if it relates every element of X to itself. An example of a reflexive relation is the relation " is equal to" on the set of real numbers, since every real number is equal to itself. A ...
, that is, A\succ A does not hold. It should also be asymmetric, that is, A\succ B implies that ''not'' B\succ A. * The notation \succeq is used when the relation is ''weak'', that is, A\succeq B means that option A is at least as good as option B (A may be equivalent to B, or better than B). In this case, the relation should be reflexive, that is, A\succeq A always holds. Given a weak preference relation \succeq, one can define its "strict part" \succ and "indifference part" \simeq as follows: * A\succ B if and only if A\succeq B and ''not'' B\succeq A. * A \simeq B if and only if A\succeq B and B\succeq A. Given a strict preference relation \succ, one can define its "weak part" \succeq and "indifference part" \simeq as follows: * A\succeq B if and only if ''not'' B \succ A; * A \simeq B if and only if ''not'' B \succ A and ''not'' A \succ B. For every option A \in X, we define the contour sets at ''A'': * Given a weak preference relation \succeq, the ''weak upper contour set at A'' is the set of all options that are at least as good as ''A'': \. The ''weak lower contour set at A'' is the set of all options that are at most as good as ''A'': \. ** A weak preference relation is called ''continuous'' if its contour sets are topologically closed. * Similarly, given a strict preference relation \succ, the ''strict upper contour set at A'' is the set of all options better than ''A'': \, and the ''strict lower contour set at A'' is the set of all options worse than ''A'': \. ** A strict preference relation is called ''continuous'' if its contour sets are topologically open. Sometimes, the above continuity notions are called ''semicontinuous'', and a \succeq is called ''continuous'' if it is a closed subset of X\times X. A preference-relation is called: * ''Countable'' - if the set of
equivalence class In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements ...
es of the indifference relation \simeq is
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
. * ''Separable'' - if there exists a countable subset Z\subseteq X such that for every pair A\succ B, there is an element z_i\in Z that separates them, that is, A \succ z_i \succ B (an analogous definition exists for weak relations). As an example, the strict order ">" on real numbers is separable, but not countable.


Utility functions

A ''utility function'' is a function u: X \to \mathbb. * A utility function ''u'' is said to ''represent'' a strict preference relation \succ, if u(A) > u(B) \iff A\succ B. * A utility function ''u'' is said to ''represent'' a weak preference relation \succeq, if u(A) \geq u(B) \iff A \succeq B.


Complete preference relations

Debreu proved the existence of a ''continuous'' representation of a weak preference relation \succeq satisfying the following conditions: # Reflexive and Transitive; #
Complete Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
, that is, for every two options ''A'', ''B'' in ''X'', either A\succeq B or B\succeq A or both; # For all A \in X, both the upper and the lower weak contour sets are topologically closed; # The space ''X'' is
second-countable In topology, a second-countable space, also called a completely separable space, is a topological space whose topology has a countable base. More explicitly, a topological space T is second-countable if there exists some countable collection \mat ...
. This means that there is a
countable set In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
''S'' of open sets, such that every open set in ''X'' is the union of sets of the class ''S''. Second-countability is implied by the following properties (from weaker to stronger): #* The space ''X'' is separable and
connected Connected may refer to: Film and television * ''Connected'' (2008 film), a Hong Kong remake of the American movie ''Cellular'' * '' Connected: An Autoblogography About Love, Death & Technology'', a 2011 documentary film * ''Connected'' (2015 TV ...
. #* The relation \succeq is separable. #* The relation \succeq is countable. Jaffray gives an elementary proof to the existence of a continuous utility function.


Incomplete preference relations

Preferences are called ''incomplete'' when some options are incomparable, that is, neither A\succeq B nor B \succeq A holds. This case is denoted by A \bowtie B. Since real numbers are always comparable, it is impossible to have a representing function ''u'' with u(A) \geq u(B) \iff A \succeq B. There are several ways to cope with this issue.


One-directional representation

Peleg defined a utility function representation of a strict partial order \succ as a function ''u: X \to \mathbb ''such thatA \succ B \implies u(A)>u(B), that is, only one direction of implication should hold. Peleg proved the existence of a one-dimensional continuous utility representation of a strict preference relation \succ satisfying the following conditions: # Irreflexive and transitive (which implies that it is asymmetric, that is, is a strict
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable ...
); # Separable; # For all A \in X, the lower strict contour set at ''A'' is topologically open; # ''Spacious'': if A\succ B, then the lower strict contour set at ''A'' contains the closure of the lower strict contour set at ''B''. #* This condition is required for incomplete preference relations. For complete preference relations, every relation in which all lower and upper strict contour sets are open, is also spacious. If we are given a weak preference relation \succeq, we can apply Peleg's theorem by defining a strict preference relation: A\succ B if and only if A\succeq B and ''not'' B\succeq A. The second condition (\succ is separable) is implied by the following three conditions: * The space ''X'' is separable; * For all A \in X, both lower and upper strict contour sets at ''A'' are topologically open; * If the lower countour set of ''A'' is nonempty, then ''A'' is in its closure. A similar approach was taken by Richter. Therefore, this one-directional representation is also called a Richter-Peleg utility representation. Jaffray defines a utility function representation of a strict partial order \succ as a function ''u: X \to \mathbb ''such that both A \succ B \implies u(A)>u(B), and A\approx B \implies u(A)=u(B), where the relation A\approx B is defined by: for all C, A\succ C \iff B\succ C and C\succ A \iff C\succ B (that is: the lower and upper contour sets of ''A'' and ''B'' are identical). He proved that, for every partially-ordered space (X, \succ) that is perfectly-separable, there exists a utility function that is upper-
semicontinuous In mathematical analysis, semicontinuity (or semi-continuity) is a property of extended real-valued functions that is weaker than continuity. An extended real-valued function f is upper (respectively, lower) semicontinuous at a point x_0 if, ro ...
in any topology stronger than the upper
order topology In mathematics, an order topology is a specific topology that can be defined on any totally ordered set. It is a natural generalization of the topology of the real numbers to arbitrary totally ordered sets. If ''X'' is a totally ordered set, ...
. An analogous statement states the existence of a utility function that is lower-semicontinuous in any topology stronger than the lower order topology. Sondermann defines a utility function representation similarly to Jaffray. He gives conditions for existence of a utility function representation on a
probability space In probability theory, a probability space or a probability triple (\Omega, \mathcal, P) is a mathematical construct that provides a formal model of a random process or "experiment". For example, one can define a probability space which models ...
, that is upper semicontinuous or lower semicontinuous in the order topology. Herdendefines a utility function representation of a weak preorder \succeq as an
isotone function In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of order ...
''u: (X, \succeq) \to (\mathbb, \geq) ''such that A \succ B \implies u(A)>u(B). Herden proved that a weak preorder \succeq on ''X'' has a continuous utility function, if and only if there exists a countable family E of separable systems on ''X'' such that, for all pairs A\succ B, there is a separable system F in E, such that B is contained in all sets in F, and A is not contained in any set in F. He shows that this theorem implies Peleg's representation theorem. In a follow-up paper he clarifies the relation between this theorem and classical utility representation theorems on complete orders.


Multi-utility representation

A ''multi-utility representation'' (MUR) of a relation \succeq is a set ''U'' of utility functions, such that A \succeq B \iff \forall u\in U: u(A)\geq u(B). In other words, ''A'' is preferred to ''B'' if and only if all utility functions in the set ''U'' unanimously hold this preference. The concept was introduced by Efe Ok. Every
preorder In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive relation, reflexive and Transitive relation, transitive. The name is meant to suggest that preorders are ''almost'' partial orders, ...
(reflexive and transitive relation) has a trivial MUR. Moreover, every preorder with closed upper contour sets has an upper-semicontinuous MUR, and every preorder with closed lower contour sets has a lower-semicontinuous MUR. However, not every preorder with closed upper and lower contour sets has a ''continuous'' MUR. Ok and Evren present several conditions on the existence of a continuous MUR: * \succeq has a continuous MUR if-and-only-if (''X'',\succeq) is a semi-normally-preordered topological space. * If ''X'' is a
locally compact In topology and related branches of mathematics, a topological space is called locally compact if, roughly speaking, each small portion of the space looks like a small portion of a compact space. More precisely, it is a topological space in which e ...
and sigma-compact
Hausdorff space In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), T2 space or separated space, is a topological space where distinct points have disjoint neighbourhoods. Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on a topologi ...
, and \succeq is a closed subset of X\times X, then \succeq has a continuous MUR. This in particular holds if ''X'' is a nonempty closed subset of a
Euclidean space Euclidean space is the fundamental space of geometry, intended to represent physical space. Originally, in Euclid's ''Elements'', it was the three-dimensional space of Euclidean geometry, but in modern mathematics there are ''Euclidean spaces ...
. * If ''X'' is any topological space, and \succeq is a preorder with closed upper and lower contour sets, that satisfies ''strong local non-satiation'' and an additional property called ''niceness'', then \succeq has a continuous MUR. All the representations guaranteed by the above theorems might contain infinitely many utilities, and even uncountably many utilities. In practice, it is often important to have a ''finite'' MUR - a MUR with finitely many utilities. Evren and Ok prove there exists a finite MUR where all utilities are upper
ower Ower is a hamlet in the New Forest district of Hampshire, England. Its nearest towns are Totton – approximately to the southeast, and Romsey – around to the north-east. Ower lies on the A36 road northwest of Totton. It lies most ...
semicontinuous for any weak preference relation \succeq satisfying the following conditions: # Reflexive and Transitive (that is, \succeq is a weak preorder); # All upper
ower Ower is a hamlet in the New Forest district of Hampshire, England. Its nearest towns are Totton – approximately to the southeast, and Romsey – around to the north-east. Ower lies on the A36 road northwest of Totton. It lies most ...
contour sets are topologically closed; # The space ''X'' is
second-countable In topology, a second-countable space, also called a completely separable space, is a topological space whose topology has a countable base. More explicitly, a topological space T is second-countable if there exists some countable collection \mat ...
, that is, it has a countable basis. # The ''width'' of \succeq (the largest size of a set in which all elements are incomparable) is finite. #* The number of utility functions in the representation is at most the width of \succeq. Note that the guaranteed functions are semicontinuous, but not necessarily continuous, even if all upper and lower contour sets are closed. Evren and Ok say that "there does not seem to be a natural way of deriving a continuous finite multi-utility representation theorem, at least, not by using the methods adopted in this paper".


See also

*
Von Neumann-Morgenstern utility theorem The term () is used in German surnames either as a nobiliary particle indicating a noble patrilineality, or as a simple preposition used by commoners that means or . Nobility directories like the often abbreviate the noble term to ''v.'' ...
* Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem *
Arrow's impossibility theorem Arrow's impossibility theorem is a key result in social choice theory showing that no ranked-choice procedure for group decision-making can satisfy the requirements of rational choice. Specifically, Arrow showed no such rule can satisfy the ind ...
*
Revealed preference Revealed preference theory, pioneered by economist Paul Anthony Samuelson in 1938, is a method of analyzing choices made by individuals, mostly used for comparing the influence of policies on consumer behavior. Revealed preference models assume th ...
theory deals with representing the
demand function In economics, an inverse demand function is the mathematical relationship that expresses price as a function of quantity demanded (it is therefore also known as a price function). Historically, the economists first expressed the price of a good a ...
of an agent by a preference relation, or by a utility function.


References

{{reflist Utility Economics theorems