Nonstandard Arithmetic
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
, a non-standard model of arithmetic is a model of first-order Peano arithmetic that contains non-standard numbers. The term standard model of arithmetic refers to the standard natural numbers 0, 1, 2, …. The elements of any model of Peano arithmetic are
linearly ordered In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( re ...
and possess an
initial segment In mathematics, an upper set (also called an upward closed set, an upset, or an isotone set in ''X'') of a partially ordered set (X, \leq) is a subset S \subseteq X with the following property: if ''s'' is in ''S'' and if ''x'' in ''X'' is larger ...
isomorphic In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping or morphism between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between the ...
to the standard natural numbers. A non-standard model is one that has additional elements outside this initial segment. The construction of such models is due to
Thoralf Skolem Thoralf Albert Skolem (; 23 May 1887 – 23 March 1963) was a Norwegian mathematician who worked in mathematical logic and set theory. Life Although Skolem's father was a primary school teacher, most of his extended family were farmers. Skole ...
(1934). Non-standard models of arithmetic exist only for the first-order formulation of the
Peano axioms In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (, ), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nea ...
; for the original second-order formulation, there is, up to isomorphism, only one model: the
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
themselves.


Existence

There are several methods that can be used to prove the existence of non-standard models of arithmetic.


From the compactness theorem

The existence of non-standard models of arithmetic can be demonstrated by an application of the
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
. To do this, a set of axioms P* is defined in a language including the language of Peano arithmetic together with a new constant symbol ''x''. The axioms consist of the axioms of Peano arithmetic P together with another infinite set of axioms: for each ''n'', the axiom ''x'' > ''n'' is included. Any finite subset of these axioms is satisfied by a model that is the standard model of arithmetic plus the constant ''x'' interpreted as some number larger than any numeral mentioned in the finite subset of P*. Thus by the compactness theorem there is a model satisfying all the axioms P*. Since any model of P* is a model of P (since a model of a set of axioms is obviously also a model of any subset of that set of axioms), we have that our extended model is also a model of the Peano axioms. The element of this model corresponding to ''x'' cannot be a standard number, because as indicated it is larger than any standard number. Using more complex methods, it is possible to build non-standard models that possess more complicated properties. For example, there are models of Peano arithmetic in which
Goodstein's theorem In mathematical logic, Goodstein's theorem is a statement about the natural numbers, proved by Reuben Goodstein in 1944, which states that every Goodstein sequence (as defined below) eventually terminates at 0. Laurence Kirby and Jeff Paris showed ...
fails. It can be proved in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
that Goodstein's theorem holds in the standard model, so a model where Goodstein's theorem fails must be non-standard.


From the incompleteness theorems

Gödel's incompleteness theorems Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the phi ...
also imply the existence of non-standard models of arithmetic. The incompleteness theorems show that a particular sentence ''G'', the Gödel sentence of Peano arithmetic, is neither provable nor disprovable in Peano arithmetic. By the
completeness theorem Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies ...
, this means that ''G'' is false in some model of Peano arithmetic. However, ''G'' is true in the standard model of arithmetic, and therefore any model in which ''G'' is false must be a non-standard model. Thus satisfying ~''G'' is a sufficient condition for a model to be nonstandard. It is not a necessary condition, however; for any Gödel sentence ''G'' and any infinite
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
there is a model of arithmetic with ''G'' true and of that cardinality.


Arithmetic unsoundness for models with ~''G'' true

Assuming that arithmetic is consistent, arithmetic with ~''G'' is also consistent. However, since ~''G'' states that arithmetic is inconsistent, the result will not be ω-consistent (because ~''G'' is false and this violates ω-consistency).


From an ultraproduct

Another method for constructing a non-standard model of arithmetic is via an
ultraproduct The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All fact ...
. A typical construction uses the set of all sequences of natural numbers, \mathbb^. Choose an
ultrafilter In the Mathematics, mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a Maximal element, maximal Filter (mathematics), filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P th ...
on \mathbb, then identify two sequences whenever they have equal values on positions that form a member of the ultrafilter (this requires that they agree on infinitely many terms, but the condition is stronger than this as ultrafilters resemble axiom-of-choice-like maximal extensions of the Fréchet filter). The resulting
semiring In abstract algebra, a semiring is an algebraic structure. Semirings are a generalization of rings, dropping the requirement that each element must have an additive inverse. At the same time, semirings are a generalization of bounded distribu ...
is a non-standard model of arithmetic. It can be identified with the
hypernatural In nonstandard analysis, a hyperinteger ''n'' is a hyperreal number that is equal to its own integer part. A hyperinteger may be either finite or infinite. A finite hyperinteger is an ordinary integer. An example of an infinite hyperinteger is ...
numbers.


Structure of countable non-standard models

The
ultraproduct The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All fact ...
models are uncountable. One way to see this is to construct an injection of the infinite product of N into the ultraproduct. However, by the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
there must exist countable non-standard models of arithmetic. One way to define such a model is to use
Henkin semantics In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies onl ...
. Any
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
non-standard model of arithmetic has
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
, where ω is the order type of the standard natural numbers, ω* is the dual order (an infinite decreasing sequence) and η is the order type of the
rational numbers In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction (mathematics), fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for examp ...
. In other words, a countable non-standard model begins with an infinite increasing sequence (the standard elements of the model). This is followed by a collection of "blocks", each of order type , the order type of the integers. These blocks are in turn densely ordered with the order type of the rationals. The result follows fairly easily because it is easy to see that the blocks of non-standard numbers have to be
dense Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the ratio of a substance's mass to its volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' (or ''d'') can also be use ...
and linearly ordered without endpoints, and the order type of the rationals is the only countable dense linear order without endpoints (see
Cantor's isomorphism theorem In order theory and model theory, branches of mathematics, Cantor's isomorphism theorem states that every two countable dense unbounded linear orders are order-isomorphic. For instance, Minkowski's question-mark function produces an isomorphis ...
).
Fred Landman Fred (Alfred) Landman (; born October 28, 1956) is a Dutch-born Israeli professor of semantics. He teaches at Tel Aviv University has written a number of books about linguistics. Biography Fred Landman was born in Holland. He immigrated to Israe ...
br>LINEAR ORDERS, DISCRETE, DENSE, AND CONTINUOUS
– includes proof that Q is the only countable dense linear order.
So, the order type of the countable non-standard models is known. However, the arithmetical operations are much more complicated. It is easy to see that the arithmetical structure differs from . For instance if a nonstandard (non-finite) element ''u'' is in the model, then so is for any ''m'' in the initial segment N, yet ''u''2 is larger than for any standard finite ''m''. Also one can define "square roots" such as the least ''v'' such that . These cannot be within a standard finite number of any rational multiple of ''u''. By analogous methods to
non-standard analysis The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using (ε, δ)-definitio ...
one can also use PA to define close approximations to irrational multiples of a non-standard number ''u'' such as the least ''v'' with (these can be defined in PA using non-standard finite rational approximations of even though itself cannot be). Once more, has to be larger than any standard finite number for any standard finite ''m'', ''n''. This shows that the arithmetical structure of a countable non-standard model is more complex than the structure of the rationals. There is more to it than that though:
Tennenbaum's theorem Tennenbaum's theorem, named for Stanley Tennenbaum who presented the theorem in 1959, is a result in mathematical logic that states that no countable nonstandard model of first-order Peano arithmetic (PA) can be recursive (Kaye 1991:153ff). Rec ...
shows that for any countable non-standard model of Peano arithmetic there is no way to code the elements of the model as (standard) natural numbers such that either the addition or multiplication operation of the model is
computable Computability is the ability to solve a problem by an effective procedure. It is a key topic of the field of computability theory within mathematical logic and the theory of computation within computer science. The computability of a problem is cl ...
on the codes. This result was first obtained by
Stanley Tennenbaum Stanley Tennenbaum (April 11, 1927 – May 4, 2005) was an American mathematician who contributed to the field of logic. In 1959, he published Tennenbaum's theorem, which states that no countable nonstandard model of Peano arithmetic (PA) can be ...
in 1959.


References


Citations


Sources

*
Boolos, George George Stephen Boolos (; September 4, 1940 – May 27, 1996) was an American philosopher and a mathematical logician who taught at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Life Boolos was of Greek-Jewish descent. He graduated with an A.B. ...
, and
Jeffrey, Richard Richard Carl Jeffrey (August 5, 1926 – November 9, 2002) was an American philosopher, logician, and probability theorist. He is best known for developing and championing the philosophy of radical probabilism and the associated heuristic of pr ...
1974. ''Computability and Logic'', Cambridge University Press. . *


See also

*
Non-Euclidean geometry In mathematics, non-Euclidean geometry consists of two geometries based on axioms closely related to those that specify Euclidean geometry. As Euclidean geometry lies at the intersection of metric geometry and affine geometry, non-Euclidean ge ...
— about non-standard models in geometry {{Mathematical logic Arithmetic Formal theories of arithmetic Mathematical logic Model theory