HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from prem ...
,
philosophy Philosophy (from , ) is the systematized study of general and fundamental questions, such as those about existence, reason, knowledge, values, mind, and language. Such questions are often posed as problems to be studied or resolved. ...
and related fields, mereology ( (root: , ''mere-'', 'part') and the suffix ''-logy'', 'study, discussion, science') is the study of parts and the wholes they form. Whereas
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
is founded on the membership relation between a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
and its elements, mereology emphasizes the meronomic relation between entities, which—from a set-theoretic perspective—is closer to the concept of inclusion between sets. Mereology has been explored in various ways as applications of predicate logic to formal ontology, in each of which mereology is an important part. Each of these fields provides its own axiomatic definition of mereology. A common element of such axiomatizations is the assumption, shared with inclusion, that the part-whole relation
orders Order, ORDER or Orders may refer to: * Categorization, the process in which ideas and objects are recognized, differentiated, and understood * Heterarchy, a system of organization wherein the elements have the potential to be ranked a number of ...
its universe, meaning that everything is a part of itself ( reflexivity), that a part of a part of a whole is itself a part of that whole ( transitivity), and that two distinct entities cannot each be a part of the other ( antisymmetry), thus forming a poset. A variant of this axiomatization denies that anything is ever part of itself (irreflexivity) while accepting transitivity, from which antisymmetry follows automatically. Although mereology is an application of
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of forma ...
, what could be argued to be a sort of "proto-geometry", it has been wholly developed by logicians, ontologists, linguists, engineers, and computer scientists, especially those working in
artificial intelligence Artificial intelligence (AI) is intelligence—perceiving, synthesizing, and inferring information—demonstrated by machines, as opposed to intelligence displayed by animals and humans. Example tasks in which this is done include speech ...
. In particular, mereology is also on the basis for a point-free foundation of geometry (see for example the quoted pioneering paper of Alfred Tarski and the review paper by Gerla 1995). In general systems theory, mereology refers to formal work on system decomposition and parts, wholes and boundaries (by, e.g., Mihajlo D. Mesarovic (1970),
Gabriel Kron Gabriel Kron (1901 – 1968) was a Hungarian American electrical engineer who promoted the use of methods of linear algebra, multilinear algebra, and differential geometry in the field. His method of system decomposition and solution called ...
(1963), or Maurice Jessel (see Bowden (1989, 1998)). A hierarchical version of
Gabriel Kron Gabriel Kron (1901 – 1968) was a Hungarian American electrical engineer who promoted the use of methods of linear algebra, multilinear algebra, and differential geometry in the field. His method of system decomposition and solution called ...
's Network Tearing was published by Keith Bowden (1991), reflecting David Lewis's ideas on gunk. Such ideas appear in theoretical
computer science Computer science is the study of computation, automation, and information. Computer science spans theoretical disciplines (such as algorithms, theory of computation, information theory, and automation) to Applied science, practical discipli ...
and
physics Physics is the natural science that studies matter, its fundamental constituents, its motion and behavior through space and time, and the related entities of energy and force. "Physical science is that department of knowledge which ...
, often in combination with sheaf theory, topos, or
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, ca ...
. See also the work of Steve Vickers on (parts of) specifications in computer science, Joseph Goguen on physical systems, and Tom Etter (1996, 1998) on link theory and
quantum mechanics Quantum mechanics is a fundamental theory in physics that provides a description of the physical properties of nature at the scale of atoms and subatomic particles. It is the foundation of all quantum physics including quantum chemistry, ...
.


History

Informal part-whole reasoning was consciously invoked in
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
and
ontology In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophy, philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, Becoming (philosophy), becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into Category ...
from
Plato Plato ( ; grc-gre, Πλάτων ; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BC) was a Greek philosopher born in Athens during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. He founded the Platonist school of thought and the Academy, the first institution ...
(in particular, in the second half of the ''
Parmenides Parmenides of Elea (; grc-gre, Παρμενίδης ὁ Ἐλεάτης; ) was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher from Elea in Magna Graecia. Parmenides was born in the Greek colony of Elea, from a wealthy and illustrious family. His date ...
'') and
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ...
onwards, and more or less unwittingly in 19th-century mathematics until the triumph of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
around 1910. Metaphysical ideas of this era that discuss the concepts of parts and wholes include
divine simplicity In theology, the doctrine of divine simplicity says that God is simple (without parts). The general idea can be stated in this way: The being of God is identical to the "attributes" of God. Characteristics such as omnipresence, goodness, trut ...
and the classical conception of beauty.
Ivor Grattan-Guinness Ivor Owen Grattan-Guinness (23 June 1941 – 12 December 2014) was a historian of mathematics and logic. Life Grattan-Guinness was born in Bakewell, England; his father was a mathematics teacher and educational administrator. He gained his b ...
(2001) sheds much light on part-whole reasoning during the 19th and early 20th centuries, and reviews how Cantor and Peano devised
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
. It appears that the first to reason consciously and at length about parts and wholes was
Edmund Husserl , thesis1_title = Beiträge zur Variationsrechnung (Contributions to the Calculus of Variations) , thesis1_url = https://fedora.phaidra.univie.ac.at/fedora/get/o:58535/bdef:Book/view , thesis1_year = 1883 , thesis2_title ...
, in 1901, in the second volume of '' Logical Investigations'' – Third Investigation: "On the Theory of Wholes and Parts" (Husserl 1970 is the English translation). However, the word "mereology" is absent from his writings, and he employed no symbolism even though his doctorate was in mathematics. Stanisław Leśniewski coined "mereology" in 1927, from the Greek word μέρος (''méros'', "part"), to refer to a formal theory of part-whole he devised in a series of highly technical papers published between 1916 and 1931, and translated in Leśniewski (1992). Leśniewski's student Alfred Tarski, in his Appendix E to Woodger (1937) and the paper translated as Tarski (1984), greatly simplified Leśniewski's formalism. Other students (and students of students) of Lesniewski elaborated this "Polish mereology" over the course of the 20th century. For a good selection of the literature on Polish mereology, see Srzednicki and Rickey (1984). For a survey of Polish mereology, see Simons (1987). Since 1980 or so, however, research on Polish mereology has been almost entirely historical in nature. A. N. Whitehead planned a fourth volume of '' Principia Mathematica'', on
geometry Geometry (; ) is, with arithmetic, one of the oldest branches of mathematics. It is concerned with properties of space such as the distance, shape, size, and relative position of figures. A mathematician who works in the field of geometry is c ...
, but never wrote it. His 1914 correspondence with
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, philosopher, logician, and public intellectual. He had a considerable influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, linguistics, a ...
reveals that his intended approach to geometry can be seen, with the benefit of hindsight, as mereological in essence. This work culminated in Whitehead (1916) and the mereological systems of Whitehead (1919, 1920). In 1930, Henry S. Leonard completed a Harvard Ph.D. dissertation in philosophy, setting out a formal theory of the part-whole relation. This evolved into the "calculus of individuals" of Goodman and Leonard (1940). Goodman revised and elaborated this calculus in the three editions of Goodman (1951). The calculus of individuals is the starting point for the post-1970 revival of mereology among logicians, ontologists, and computer scientists, a revival well-surveyed in Simons (1987), Casati and Varzi (1999), and Cotnoir and Varzi (2021).


Axioms and primitive notions

Reflexivity: A basic choice in defining a mereological system, is whether to consider things to be parts of themselves. In
naive set theory Naive set theory is any of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics. Unlike axiomatic set theories, which are defined using formal logic, naive set theory is defined informally, in natural language. It ...
a similar question arises: whether a set is to be considered a "subset" of itself. In both cases, "yes" gives rise to paradoxes analogous to Russell's paradox: Let there be an object O such that every object that is not a proper part of itself is a proper part of O. Is O a proper part of itself? No, because no object is a proper part of itself; and yes, because it meets the specified requirement for inclusion as a proper part of O. In set theory, a set is often termed an ''improper'' subset of itself. Given such paradoxes, mereology requires an axiomatic formulation. A mereological "system" is a
first-order theory First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quan ...
(with
identity Identity may refer to: * Identity document * Identity (philosophy) * Identity (social science) * Identity (mathematics) Arts and entertainment Film and television * ''Identity'' (1987 film), an Iranian film * ''Identity'' (2003 film), an ...
) whose universe of discourse consists of wholes and their respective parts, collectively called ''objects''. Mereology is a collection of nested and non-nested axiomatic systems, not unlike the case with
modal logic Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend ot ...
. The treatment, terminology, and hierarchical organization below follow Casati and Varzi (1999: Ch. 3) closely. For a more recent treatment, correcting certain misconceptions, see Hovda (2008). Lower-case letters denote variables ranging over objects. Following each symbolic axiom or definition is the number of the corresponding formula in Casati and Varzi, written in bold. A mereological system requires at least one primitive
binary relation In mathematics, a binary relation associates elements of one set, called the ''domain'', with elements of another set, called the ''codomain''. A binary relation over sets and is a new set of ordered pairs consisting of elements in and in ...
( dyadic
predicate Predicate or predication may refer to: * Predicate (grammar), in linguistics * Predication (philosophy) * several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic: **Predicate (mathematical logic) **Propositional function **Finitary relation, o ...
). The most conventional choice for such a relation is parthood (also called "inclusion"), "''x'' is a ''part'' of ''y''", written ''Pxy''. Nearly all systems require that parthood partially order the universe. The following defined relations, required for the axioms below, follow immediately from parthood alone: *An immediate defined
predicate Predicate or predication may refer to: * Predicate (grammar), in linguistics * Predication (philosophy) * several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic: **Predicate (mathematical logic) **Propositional function **Finitary relation, o ...
is "x is a proper part of ''y''", written ''PPxy'', which holds (i.e., is satisfied, comes out true) if ''Pxy'' is true and ''Pyx'' is false. Compared to parthood (which is a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary ...
), ProperPart is a strict partial order. :PPxy \leftrightarrow (Pxy \land \lnot Pyx). 3.3 :An object lacking proper parts is an ''atom''. The mereological
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents, including planets, stars, galaxies, and all other forms of matter and energy. The Big Bang theory is the prevailing cosmological description of the development of the univers ...
consists of all objects we wish to think about, and all of their proper parts: *Overlap: ''x'' and ''y'' overlap, written ''Oxy'', if there exists an object ''z'' such that ''Pzx'' and ''Pzy'' both hold. :Oxy \leftrightarrow \exists z zx \land Pzy 3.1 :The parts of ''z'', the "overlap" or "product" of ''x'' and ''y'', are precisely those objects that are parts of both ''x'' and ''y''. *Underlap: ''x'' and ''y'' underlap, written ''Uxy'', if there exists an object ''z'' such that ''x'' and ''y'' are both parts of ''z''. :Uxy \leftrightarrow \exists z xz \land Pyz 3.2 Overlap and Underlap are reflexive, symmetric, and intransitive. Systems vary in what relations they take as primitive and as defined. For example, in extensional mereologies (defined below), ''parthood'' can be defined from Overlap as follows: :Pxy \leftrightarrow \forall z zx \rightarrow Ozy 3.31 The axioms are: *Parthood partially orders the
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents, including planets, stars, galaxies, and all other forms of matter and energy. The Big Bang theory is the prevailing cosmological description of the development of the univers ...
: :M1, Reflexive: An object is a part of itself. :\ Pxx. P.1 :M2, Antisymmetric: If ''Pxy'' and ''Pyx'' both hold, then ''x'' and ''y'' are the same object. :(Pxy \land Pyx) \rightarrow x = y. P.2 :M3, Transitive: If ''Pxy'' and ''Pyz'', then ''Pxz''. :(Pxy \land Pyz) \rightarrow Pxz. P.3 *M4, Weak Supplementation: If ''PPxy'' holds, there exists a ''z'' such that ''Pzy'' holds but ''Ozx'' does not. :PPxy \rightarrow \exists z zy \land \lnot Ozx P.4 *M5, Strong Supplementation: If ''Pyx'' does not hold, there exists a ''z'' such that ''Pzy'' holds but ''Ozx'' does not. :\lnot Pyx \rightarrow \exists z zy \land \lnot Ozx P.5 *M5', Atomistic Supplementation: If ''Pxy'' does not hold, then there exists an atom ''z'' such that ''Pzx'' holds but ''Ozy'' does not. :\lnot Pxy \rightarrow \exists z zx \land \lnot Ozy \land \lnot \exists v [PPvz. P.5' *Top: There exists a "universal object", designated ''W'', such that ''PxW'' holds for any ''x''. :\exists W \forall x [PxW]. 3.20 :Top is a theorem if M8 holds. *Bottom: There exists an atomic "null object", designated ''N'', such that ''PNx'' holds for any ''x''. :\exists N \forall x [PNx]. 3.22 *M6, Sum: If ''Uxy'' holds, there exists a ''z'', called the "sum" or "fusion" of ''x'' and ''y'', such that the objects overlapping of ''z'' are just those objects that overlap either ''x'' or ''y''. :Uxy \rightarrow \exists z \forall v vz \leftrightarrow (Ovx \lor Ovy) P.6 *M7, Product: If ''Oxy'' holds, there exists a ''z'', called the "product" of ''x'' and ''y'', such that the parts of ''z'' are just those objects that are parts of both ''x'' and ''y''. :Oxy \rightarrow \exists z \forall v vz \leftrightarrow (Pvx \land Pvy) P.7 :If ''Oxy'' does not hold, ''x'' and ''y'' have no parts in common, and the product of ''x'' and ''y'' is undefined. *M8, Unrestricted Fusion: Let φ(''x'') be a
first-order In mathematics and other formal sciences, first-order or first order most often means either: * "linear" (a polynomial of degree at most one), as in first-order approximation and other calculus uses, where it is contrasted with "polynomials of hig ...
formula in which ''x'' is a free variable. Then the fusion of all objects satisfying φ exists. :\exists x phi(x)\to \exists z \forall y yz_\leftrightarrow_\exists_x[\phi_(x)_\land_Oyx._P.8 :M8_is_also_called_"General_Sum_Principle",_"Unrestricted_Mereological_Composition",_or_"Universalism"._M8_corresponds_to_the_set_builder_notation.html" ;"title="phi_(x)_\land_Oyx.html" ;"title="yz \leftrightarrow \exists x yz_\leftrightarrow_\exists_x[\phi_(x)_\land_Oyx._P.8 :M8_is_also_called_"General_Sum_Principle",_"Unrestricted_Mereological_Composition",_or_"Universalism"._M8_corresponds_to_the_set_builder_notation">principle_of_unrestricted_comprehension_of_naive_set_theory_ Naive_set_theory_is_any_of_several_theories_of_sets_used_in_the_discussion_of_the__foundations_of_mathematics. Unlike__axiomatic_set_theories,_which_are_defined_using__formal_logic,_naive_set_theory_is_defined_informally,_in__natural_language._It_...
,_which_gives_rise_to__Russell's_paradox._There_is_no_mereological_counterpart_to_this_paradox_simply_because_''parthood'',_unlike_set_membership,_is_Reflexive_relation.html" ;"title="phi (x) \land Oyx">yz \leftrightarrow \exists x[\phi (x) \land Oyx. P.8 :M8 is also called "General Sum Principle", "Unrestricted Mereological Composition", or "Universalism". M8 corresponds to the set builder notation">principle of unrestricted comprehension of
naive set theory Naive set theory is any of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics. Unlike axiomatic set theories, which are defined using formal logic, naive set theory is defined informally, in natural language. It ...
, which gives rise to Russell's paradox. There is no mereological counterpart to this paradox simply because ''parthood'', unlike set membership, is Reflexive relation">reflexive. *M8', Unique Fusion: The fusions whose existence M8 asserts are also unique. P.8' *M9, Atomicity: All objects are either atoms or fusions of atoms. : \exists y[Pyx \land \forall z[\lnot PPzy. P.10


Various systems

Simons (1987), Casati and Varzi (1999) and Hovda (2008) describe many mereological systems whose axioms are taken from the above list. We adopt the boldface nomenclature of Casati and Varzi. The best-known such system is the one called ''classical extensional mereology'', hereinafter abbreviated CEM (other abbreviations are explained below). In CEM, P.1 through P.8' hold as axioms or are theorems. M9, ''Top'', and ''Bottom'' are optional. The systems in the table below are partially ordered by inclusion, in the sense that, if all the theorems of system A are also theorems of system B, but the converse is not necessarily true, then B ''includes'' A. The resulting Hasse diagram is similar to Fig. 3.2 in Casati and Varzi (1999: 48). There are two equivalent ways of asserting that the
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents, including planets, stars, galaxies, and all other forms of matter and energy. The Big Bang theory is the prevailing cosmological description of the development of the univers ...
is partially ordered: Assume either M1-M3, or that Proper Parthood is transitive and asymmetric, hence a strict partial order. Either axiomatization results in the system M. M2 rules out closed loops formed using Parthood, so that the part relation is well-founded. Sets are well-founded if the
axiom of regularity In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every non-empty set ''A'' contains an element that is disjoint from ''A''. In first-order logic, the a ...
is assumed. The literature contains occasional philosophical and common-sense objections to the transitivity of Parthood. M4 and M5 are two ways of asserting supplementation, the mereological analog of set complementation, with M5 being stronger because M4 is derivable from M5. M and M4 yield ''minimal'' mereology, MM. Reformulated in terms of Proper Part, MM is Simons's (1987) preferred minimal system. In any system in which M5 or M5' are assumed or can be derived, then it can be proved that two objects having the same proper parts are identical. This property is known as '' Extensionality'', a term borrowed from set theory, for which extensionality is the defining axiom. Mereological systems in which Extensionality holds are termed ''extensional'', a fact denoted by including the letter E in their symbolic names. M6 asserts that any two underlapping objects have a unique sum; M7 asserts that any two overlapping objects have a unique product. If the universe is finite or if ''Top'' is assumed, then the universe is closed under ''Sum''. Universal closure of ''Product'' and of supplementation relative to ''W'' requires ''Bottom''. ''W'' and ''N'' are, evidently, the mereological analog of the
universal Universal is the adjective for universe. Universal may also refer to: Companies * NBCUniversal, a media and entertainment company ** Universal Animation Studios, an American Animation studio, and a subsidiary of NBCUniversal ** Universal TV, a t ...
and
empty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in othe ...
s, and ''Sum'' and ''Product'' are, likewise, the analogs of set-theoretical union and
intersection In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, thei ...
. If M6 and M7 are either assumed or derivable, the result is a mereology with closure. Because ''Sum'' and ''Product'' are binary operations, M6 and M7 admit the sum and product of only a finite number of objects. The ''Unrestricted Fusion'' axiom, M8, enables taking the sum of infinitely many objects. The same holds for ''Product'', when defined. At this point, mereology often invokes
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
, but any recourse to set theory is eliminable by replacing a formula with a quantified variable ranging over a universe of sets by a schematic formula with one free variable. The formula comes out true (is satisfied) whenever the name of an object that would be a
member Member may refer to: * Military jury, referred to as "Members" in military jargon * Element (mathematics), an object that belongs to a mathematical set * In object-oriented programming, a member of a class ** Field (computer science), entries in ...
of the set (if it existed) replaces the free variable. Hence any axiom with sets can be replaced by an axiom schema with monadic atomic subformulae. M8 and M8' are schemas of just this sort. The
syntax In linguistics, syntax () is the study of how words and morphemes combine to form larger units such as phrases and sentences. Central concerns of syntax include word order, grammatical relations, hierarchical sentence structure ( constituenc ...
of a
first-order theory First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quan ...
can describe only a denumerable number of sets; hence, only denumerably many sets may be eliminated in this fashion, but this limitation is not binding for the sort of mathematics contemplated here. If M8 holds, then ''W'' exists for infinite universes. Hence, ''Top'' need be assumed only if the universe is infinite and M8 does not hold. ''Top'' (postulating ''W'') is not controversial, but ''Bottom'' (postulating ''N'') is. Leśniewski rejected ''Bottom'', and most mereological systems follow his example (an exception is the work of Richard Milton Martin). Hence, while the universe is closed under sum, the product of objects that do not overlap is typically undefined. A system with ''W'' but not ''N'' is isomorphic to: * a
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
lacking a 0; * a
join Join may refer to: * Join (law), to include additional counts or additional defendants on an indictment *In mathematics: ** Join (mathematics), a least upper bound of sets orders in lattice theory ** Join (topology), an operation combining two topo ...
semilattice bounded from above by 1. Binary fusion and ''W'' interpret join and 1, respectively. Postulating ''N'' renders all possible products definable, but also transforms classical extensional mereology into a set-free model of
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
. If sets are admitted, M8 asserts the existence of the fusion of all members of any nonempty set. Any mereological system in which M8 holds is called ''general'', and its name includes G. In any general mereology, M6 and M7 are provable. Adding M8 to an extensional mereology results in ''general extensional mereology'', abbreviated GEM; moreover, the extensionality renders the fusion unique. On the converse, however, if the fusion asserted by M8 is assumed unique, so that M8' replaces M8, then—as Tarski (1929) had shown—M3 and M8' suffice to axiomatize GEM, a remarkably economical result. Simons (1987: 38–41) lists a number of GEM theorems. M2 and a finite universe necessarily imply ''Atomicity'', namely that everything either is an atom or includes atoms among its proper parts. If the universe is infinite, ''Atomicity'' requires M9. Adding M9 to any mereological system, X results in the atomistic variant thereof, denoted AX. ''Atomicity'' permits economies, for instance, assuming that M5' implies ''Atomicity'' and extensionality, and yields an alternative axiomatization of AGEM.


Set theory

The notion of "subset" in set theory is not entirely the same as the notion of "subpart" in mereology. Stanisław Leśniewski rejected set theory as related to but not the same as
nominalism In metaphysics, nominalism is the view that universals and abstract objects do not actually exist other than being merely names or labels. There are at least two main versions of nominalism. One version denies the existence of universalsthings ...
. For a long time, nearly all philosophers and mathematicians avoided mereology, seeing it as tantamount to a rejection of set theory. Goodman too was a nominalist, and his fellow nominalist Richard Milton Martin employed a version of the calculus of individuals throughout his career, starting in 1941. Much early work on mereology was motivated by a suspicion that
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
was ontologically suspect, and that Occam's razor requires that one minimise the number of posits in one's theory of the world and of mathematics. Mereology replaces talk of "sets" of objects with talk of "sums" of objects, objects being no more than the various things that make up wholes. Many logicians and philosophers reject these motivations, on such grounds as: * They deny that sets are in any way ontologically suspect * Occam's razor, when applied to abstract objects like sets, is either a dubious principle or simply false * Mereology itself is guilty of proliferating new and ontologically suspect entities such as fusions. For a survey of attempts to found mathematics without using set theory, see Burgess and Rosen (1997). In the 1970s, thanks in part to Eberle (1970), it gradually came to be understood that one can employ mereology regardless of one's ontological stance regarding sets. This understanding is called the "ontological innocence" of mereology. This innocence stems from mereology being formalizable in either of two equivalent ways: *Quantified variables ranging over a
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents, including planets, stars, galaxies, and all other forms of matter and energy. The Big Bang theory is the prevailing cosmological description of the development of the univers ...
of sets *Schematic Predicate (mathematical logic), predicates with a single free variable. Once it became clear that mereology is not tantamount to a denial of set theory, mereology became largely accepted as a useful tool for formal
ontology In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophy, philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, Becoming (philosophy), becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into Category ...
and
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
. In set theory, Singleton (mathematics), singletons are "atoms" that have no (non-empty) proper parts; many consider set theory useless or incoherent (not "well-founded") if sets cannot be built up from unit sets. The calculus of individuals was thought to require that an object either have no proper parts, in which case it is an "atom", or be the mereological sum of atoms. Eberle (1970), however, showed how to construct a calculus of individuals lacking "Atomism, atoms", i.e., one where every object has a "proper part" (defined below) so that the
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents, including planets, stars, galaxies, and all other forms of matter and energy. The Big Bang theory is the prevailing cosmological description of the development of the univers ...
is infinite. There are analogies between the axioms of mereology and those of standard Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF), if ''Parthood'' is taken as analogous to subset in set theory. On the relation of mereology and ZF, also see Bunt (1985). One of the very few contemporary set theorists to discuss mereology is Potter (2004). David Lewis (philosopher), Lewis (1991) went further, showing informally that mereology, augmented by a few ontology, ontological assumptions and plural quantification, and some novel reasoning about Singleton (mathematics), singletons, yields a system in which a given individual can be both a part and a subset of another individual. Various sorts of set theory can be interpreted in the resulting systems. For example, the axioms of ZFC can be proven given some additional mereological assumptions. Forrest (2002) revises Lewis's analysis by first formulating a generalization of CEM, called "Heyting mereology", whose sole nonlogical primitive is ''Proper Part'', assumed transitive relation, transitive and antireflexive. There exists a "fictitious" null individual that is a proper part of every individual. Two schemas assert that every lattice (order), lattice join exists (lattices are complete lattice, complete) and that meet distributive property, distributes over join. On this Heyting mereology, Forrest erects a theory of ''pseudosets'', adequate for all purposes to which sets have been put.


Mathematics

Husserl never claimed that mathematics could or should be grounded in part-whole rather than set theory. Lesniewski consciously derived his mereology as an alternative to set theory as a foundation of mathematics, but did not work out the details. Goodman and W. V. O. Quine, Quine (1947) tried to develop the natural numbers, natural and real numbers using the calculus of individuals, but were mostly unsuccessful; Quine did not reprint that article in his ''Selected Logic Papers''. In a series of chapters in the books he published in the last decade of his life, Richard Milton Martin set out to do what Goodman and Quine had abandoned 30 years prior. A recurring problem with attempts to ground mathematics in mereology is how to build up the theory of Relation (mathematics), relations while abstaining from set-theoretic definitions of the ordered pair. Martin argued that Eberle's (1970) theory of relational individuals solved this problem. Topology, Topological notions of Boundary (topology), boundaries and connection can be married to mereology, resulting in mereotopology; see Casati and Varzi (1999: ch. 4,5). Whitehead's 1929 ''Process and Reality'' contains a good deal of informal mereotopology.


Natural language

Bunt (1985), a study of the semantics of natural language, shows how mereology can help understand such phenomena as the mass noun, mass–count distinction and grammatical aspect, verb aspect. But Nicolas (2008) argues that a different logical framework, called Plural quantification, plural logic, should be used for that purpose. Also, natural language often employs "part of" in ambiguous ways (Simons 1987 discusses this at length). Hence, it is unclear how, if at all, one can translate certain natural language expressions into mereological predicates. Steering clear of such difficulties may require limiting the interpretation of mereology to mathematics and natural science. Casati and Varzi (1999), for example, limit the scope of mereology to physical objects.


Metaphysics

In
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
there are many troubling questions pertaining to parts and wholes. One question addresses constitution and persistence, another asks about composition.


Mereological constitution

In metaphysics, there are several puzzles concerning cases of mereological constitution, that is, what makes up a whole. There is still a concern with parts and wholes, but instead of looking at what parts make up a whole, the emphasis is on what a thing is made of, such as its materials, e.g., the bronze in a bronze statue. Below are two of the main puzzles that philosophers use to discuss constitution. ''Ship of Theseus:'' Briefly, the puzzle goes something like this. There is a ship called the Ship of Theseus. Over time, the boards start to rot, so we remove the boards and place them in a pile. First question, is the ship made of the new boards the same as the ship that had all the old boards? Second, if we reconstruct a ship using all of the old planks, etc. from the Ship of Theseus, and we also have a ship that was built out of new boards (each added one-by-one over time to replace old decaying boards), which ship is the real Ship of Theseus? ''Statue and Lump of Clay:'' Roughly, a sculptor decides to mold a statue out of a lump of clay. At time t1 the sculptor has a lump of clay. After many manipulations at time t2 there is a statue. The question asked is, is the lump of clay and the statue (numerically) identical? If so, how and why? Constitution typically has implications for views on persistence: how does an object persist over time if any of its parts (materials) change or are removed, as is the case with humans who lose cells, change height, hair color, memories, and yet we are said to be the same person today as we were when we were first born. For example, Ted Sider is the same today as he was when he was born—he just changed. But how can this be if many parts of Ted today did not exist when Ted was just born? Is it possible for things, such as organisms to persist? And if so, how? There are several views that attempt to answer this question. Some of the views are as follows (note, there are several other views): (a) Constitution view. This view accepts cohabitation. That is, two objects share exactly the same matter. Here, it follows, that there are no temporal parts. (b) Mereological essentialism, which states that the only objects that exist are quantities of matter, which are things defined by their parts. The object persists if matter is removed (or the form changes); but the object ceases to exist if any matter is destroyed. (c) Dominant Sorts. This is the view that tracing is determined by which sort is dominant; they reject cohabitation. For example, lump does not equal statue because they're different "sorts". (d) Nihilism—which makes the claim that no objects exist, except simples, so there is no persistence problem. (e) Four-dimensionalism, 4-dimensionalism or temporal parts (may also go by the names perdurantism or Four-dimensionalism, exdurantism), which roughly states that aggregates of temporal parts are intimately related. For example, two roads merging, momentarily and spatially, are still one road, because they share a part. (f) 3-dimensionalism (may also go by the name endurantism), where the object is wholly present. That is, the persisting object retains numerical identity.


Mereological composition

One question that is addressed by philosophers is which is more fundamental: parts, wholes, or neither? Another pressing question is called the special composition question (SCQ): For any Xs, when is it the case that there is a Y such that the Xs compose Y? This question has caused philosophers to run in three different directions: nihilism, universal composition (UC), or a moderate view (restricted composition). The first two views are considered extreme since the first denies composition, and the second allows any and all non-spatially overlapping objects to compose another object. The moderate view encompasses several theories that try to make sense of SCQ without saying 'no' to composition or 'yes' to unrestricted composition.


Fundamentality

There are philosophers who are concerned with the question of fundamentality. That is, which is more ontologically fundamental the parts or their wholes. There are several responses to this question, though one of the default assumptions is that the parts are more fundamental. That is, the whole is grounded in its parts. This is the mainstream view. Another view, explored by Schaffer (2010) is monism, where the parts are grounded in the whole. Schaffer does not just mean that, say, the parts that make up my body are grounded in my body. Rather, Schaffer argues that the whole ''cosmos'' is more fundamental and everything else is a part of the cosmos. Then, there is the identity theory which claims that there is no hierarchy or fundamentality to parts and wholes. Instead wholes ''are just'' (or equivalent to) their parts. There can also be a two-object view which says that the wholes are not equal to the parts—they are numerically distinct from one another. Each of these theories has benefits and costs associated with them.


Special composition question (SCQ)

Philosophers want to know when some Xs compose something Y. There are several kinds of responses: *One response to this question is called ''nihilism''. Nihilism states that there are no mereological complex objects (read: composite objects); there are only simples (philosophy), simples. Nihilists do not entirely reject composition because they do think that simples compose themselves, but this is a different point. More formally Nihilists would say: Necessarily, for any non-overlapping Xs, there is an object composed of the Xs if and only if there is only one of the Xs. This theory, though well explored, has its own set of problems. Some of which include, but are not limited to: experiences and common sense, incompatible with atomless gunk, and it is unsupported by space-time physics. *Another prominent response is called ''universal composition'' (UC). UC says that so long as the Xs do not spatially overlap, the Xs can compose a complex object. Universal compositionalists are also considered those who support unrestricted composition. More formally: Necessarily, for any non-overlapping Xs, there is a Y such that Y is composed of the Xs. For example, someone's left thumb, the top half of another person's right shoe, and a quark in the center of their galaxy can compose a complex object according to universal composition. Likewise, this theory also has some issues, most of them dealing with our experiences that these randomly chosen parts make up a complex whole and there are far too many objects posited in our ontology. *A third response (perhaps less explored than the previous two) includes a range of ''restricted composition views''. Though there are several views, they all share a common idea: that there is a restriction on what counts as a complex object: some (but not all) Xs come together to compose a complex Y. Some of these theories include: (a) Contact—the Xs compose a complex Y if and only if the Xs are in contact; (b) Fastenation—the Xs compose a complex Y if and only if the Xs are fastened; (c) Cohesion—the Xs compose a complex Y if and only if the Xs cohere (cannot be pulled apart or moved in relation to each other without breaking); (d) Fusion—the Xs compose a complex Y if and only if the Xs are fused (fusion is when the Xs are joined together such that there is no boundary); (e) Organicism—the Xs compose a complex Y if and only if either the activities of the Xs constitute a life or there is only one of the Xs; and (f) Brutal Composition—"It's just the way things are." There is no true, nontrivial, and finitely long answer. This is not an exhaustive list as many more hypotheses continue to be explored. However, a common problem with these theories is that they are vague. It remains unclear what "fastened" or "life" mean, for example. But there are many other issues within the restricted composition responses—though many of them are subject to which theory is being discussed. * A fourth response is called ''deflationism''. Deflationism states that there is variance on how the term "exist" is used, and thus all of the above answers to the SCQ can be correct when indexed to a favorable meaning of "exist." Further, there is no privileged way in which the term "exist" must be used. There is therefore no privileged answer to the SCQ, since there are no privileged conditions for when X composes Y. Instead, the debate is reduced to a mere verbal dispute rather than a genuine ontological debate. In this way, the SCQ is part of a larger debate in general ontological realism and anti-realism. While deflationism successfully avoids the SCQ, it is not devoid of problems. It comes with the cost of ontological anti-realism such that nature has no objective reality at all. For, if there is no privileged way to objectively affirm the existence of objects, nature itself must have no objectivity.


Important surveys

The books by Simons (1987) and Casati and Varzi (1999) differ in their strengths: *Simons (1987) sees mereology primarily as a way of formalizing
ontology In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophy, philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, Becoming (philosophy), becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into Category ...
and
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
. His strengths include the connections between mereology and: **The work of Stanisław Leśniewski and his descendants **Various continental philosophers, especially
Edmund Husserl , thesis1_title = Beiträge zur Variationsrechnung (Contributions to the Calculus of Variations) , thesis1_url = https://fedora.phaidra.univie.ac.at/fedora/get/o:58535/bdef:Book/view , thesis1_year = 1883 , thesis2_title ...
**Contemporary English-speaking technical philosophers such as Kit Fine and Roderick Chisholm **Recent work on formal ontology and
metaphysics Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that studies the fundamental nature of reality, the first principles of being, identity and change, space and time, causality, necessity, and possibility. It includes questions about the nature of conscio ...
, including continuants, occurrents, class nouns, mass nouns, and ontological dependence and integrity **Free logic as a background logic **Extending mereology with tense logic and
modal logic Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend ot ...
**
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
s and lattice theory. *Casati and Varzi (1999) see mereology primarily as a way of understanding the material world and how humans interact with it. Their strengths include the connections between mereology and: ** A "proto-geometry" for physical objects ** Topology and mereotopology, especially Boundary (topology), boundaries, regions, and holes ** A formal theory of events ** Theoretical
computer science Computer science is the study of computation, automation, and information. Computer science spans theoretical disciplines (such as algorithms, theory of computation, information theory, and automation) to Applied science, practical discipli ...
** The writings of Alfred North Whitehead, especially his ''Process and Reality'' and work descended therefrom.Cf. Peter Simons, "Whitehead and Mereology", in Guillaume Durand et Michel Weber (éditeurs),
Les principes de la connaissance naturelle d’Alfred North Whitehead — Alfred North Whitehead’s Principles of Natural Knowledge
', Frankfurt / Paris / Lancaster, ontos verlag, 2007. See also the relevant entries of Michel Weber and Will Desmond, (eds.),
Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought
', Frankfurt / Lancaster, ontos verlag, Process Thought X1 & X2, 2008.
Simons devotes considerable effort to elucidating historical notations. The notation of Casati and Varzi is often used. Both books include excellent bibliographies. To these works should be added Hovda (2008), which presents the latest state of the art on the axiomatization of mereology.


See also

* Finitist set theory * Gunk (mereology) * Implicate and explicate order according to David Bohm * ''Laws of Form'' by G. Spencer-Brown * Mereological essentialism * Mereological nihilism * Mereotopology * Meronomy * Meronymy * Monad (philosophy) * Plural quantification * Quantifier variance * Simple (philosophy) * Whitehead's point-free geometry * Composition (objects)


References


Sources

* Bowden, Keith, 1991. ''Hierarchical Tearing: An Efficient Holographic Algorithm for System Decomposition'', Int. J. General Systems, Vol. 24(1), pp 23–38. * Bowden, Keith, 1998. ''Huygens Principle, Physics and Computers''. Int. J. General Systems, Vol. 27(1-3), pp. 9–32. * Bunt, Harry, 1985. ''Mass terms and model-theoretic semantics''. Cambridge Univ. Press. * John P. Burgess, Burgess, John P., and Gideon Rosen, Rosen, Gideon, 1997. ''A Subject with No Object''. Oxford Univ. Press. * Burkhardt, H., and Dufour, C.A., 1991, "Part/Whole I: History" in Burkhardt, H., and Smith, B., eds., ''Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology''. Muenchen: Philosophia Verlag. * Casati, Roberto, and Achille Varzi (philosopher), Varzi, Achille C., 1999. ''Parts and Places: the structures of spatial representation''. MIT Press. * Cotnoir, A. J., and Achille Varzi (philosopher), Varzi, Achille C., 2021, ''Mereology'', Oxford University Press. * Eberle, Rolf, 1970. ''Nominalistic Systems''. Kluwer. * Etter, Tom, 1996. ''Quantum Mechanics as a Branch of Mereology'' in Toffoli T., ''et al.'', ''PHYSCOMP96, Proceedings of the Fourth Workshop on Physics and Computation'', New England Complex Systems Institute. * Etter, Tom, 1998. ''Process, System, Causality and Quantum Mechanics''. SLAC-PUB-7890, Stanford Linear Accelerator Centre. * Peter Forrest (philosopher), Forrest, Peter, 2002,
Nonclassical mereology and its application to sets
, ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 43'': 79–94. * Gerla, Giangiacomo, (1995).
Pointless Geometries
, in Buekenhout, F., Kantor, W. eds., "Handbook of incidence geometry: buildings and foundations". North-Holland: 1015–31. * Nelson Goodman, Goodman, Nelson, 1977 (1951). ''The Structure of Appearance''. Kluwer. * Nelson Goodman, Goodman, Nelson, and Willard Quine, Quine, Willard, 1947, "Steps toward a constructive nominalism", ''Journal of Symbolic Logic'' 12: 97-122. * Gruszczynski, R., and Pietruszczak, A., 2008,
Full development of Tarski's geometry of solids
, ''Bulletin of Symbolic Logic'' 14: 481–540. A system of geometry based on Lesniewski's mereology, with basic properties of mereological structures. * Hovda, Paul, 2008,
What is classical mereology?
''Journal of Philosophical Logic'' 38(1): 55–82. * Edmund Husserl, Husserl, Edmund, 1970. ''Logical Investigations, Vol. 2''. Findlay, J.N., trans. Routledge. * Kron, Gabriel, 1963, ''Diakoptics: The Piecewise Solution of Large Scale Systems''. Macdonald, London. * David Lewis (philosopher), Lewis, David K., 1991. ''Parts of Classes''. Blackwell. * Leonard, H. S., and Nelson Goodman, Goodman, Nelson, 1940, "The calculus of individuals and its uses", ''Journal of Symbolic Logic 5'': 45–55. * Stanisław Leśniewski, Leśniewski, Stanisław, 1992. ''Collected Works''. Surma, S.J., Srzednicki, J.T., Barnett, D.I., and Rickey, V.F., editors and translators. Kluwer. *John Lucas (philosopher), Lucas, J. R., 2000. ''Conceptual Roots of Mathematics''. Routledge. Ch. 9.12 and 10 discuss mereology, mereotopology, and the related theories of A.N. Whitehead, all strongly influenced by the unpublished writings of David Bostock (philosopher), David Bostock. * Mesarovic, M.D., Macko, D., and Takahara, Y., 1970, "Theory of Multilevel, Hierarchical Systems". Academic Press. * Nicolas, David, 2008,
Mass nouns and plural logic
, ''Linguistics and Philosophy'' 31(2): 211–44. * Pietruszczak, Andrzej, 1996,
Mereological sets of distributive classes
, ''Logic and Logical Philosophy'' 4: 105–22. Constructs, using mereology, mathematical entities from set theoretical classes. * Pietruszczak, Andrzej, 2005,
Pieces of mereology
, ''Logic and Logical Philosophy'' 14: 211–34. Basic mathematical properties of Lesniewski's mereology. * Pietruszczak, Andrzej, 2018, ''Metamerology'', Nicolaus Copernicus University Scientific Publishing House. * Potter, Michael, 2004. '' Set Theory and Its Philosophy''. Oxford Univ. Press. * Peter Simons (academic), Simons, Peter, 1987 (reprinted 2000). ''Parts: A Study in Ontology''. Oxford Univ. Press. * Srzednicki, J. T. J., and Rickey, V. F., eds., 1984. ''Lesniewski's Systems: Ontology and Mereology''. Kluwer. * Alfred Tarski, Tarski, Alfred, 1984 (1956), "Foundations of the Geometry of Solids" in his ''Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers 1923–38''. Woodger, J., and Corcoran, J., eds. and trans. Hackett. * Achille Varzi (philosopher), Varzi, Achille C., 2007,
Spatial Reasoning and Ontology: Parts, Wholes, and Locations
in Aiello, M. et al., eds., ''Handbook of Spatial Logics''. Springer-Verlag: 945–1038. * A. N. Whitehead, Whitehead, A. N., 1916, "La Theorie Relationiste de l'Espace", ''Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 23'': 423–454. Translated as Hurley, P.J., 1979, "The relational theory of space", ''Philosophy Research Archives 5'': 712–741. *------, 1919. ''An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge''. Cambridge Univ. Press. 2nd ed., 1925. *------, 1920. ''The Concept of Nature''. Cambridge Univ. Press. 2004 paperback, Prometheus Books. Being the 1919 Tarner Lectures delivered at Trinity College, Cambridge. *------, 1978 (1929). ''Process and Reality''. Free Press. * Joseph Henry Woodger, Woodger, J. H., 1937. ''The Axiomatic Method in Biology''. Cambridge Univ. Press.


External links

* * *Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: *
Material Composition
– David Cornell *Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: *
Mereology
– Achille Varzi *
Boundary
– Achille Varzi {{Authority control Mereology, Mathematical logic Ontology Predicate logic Semantic relations