HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Of the many and varied
argument form In logic, logical form of a Statement (logic), statement is a precisely-specified Semantics, semantic version of that statement in a formal system. Informally, the logical form attempts to formalize a possibly Syntactic ambiguity, ambiguous sta ...
s that can possibly be constructed, only very few are valid argument forms. In order to evaluate these forms,
statements Statement or statements may refer to: Common uses *Statement (computer science), the smallest standalone element of an imperative programming language *Statement (logic), declarative sentence that is either true or false *Statement, a declarative ...
are put into
logical form In logic, logical form of a statement is a precisely-specified semantic version of that statement in a formal system. Informally, the logical form attempts to formalize a possibly ambiguous statement into a statement with a precise, unambi ...
. Logical form replaces any sentences or ideas with letters to remove any bias from content and allow one to evaluate the argument without any bias due to its subject matter. Being a valid argument does not necessarily mean the conclusion will be true. It is valid because if the premises are true, then the conclusion has to be true. This can be proven for any valid argument form using a
truth table A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional argumen ...
which shows that there is no situation in which there are all true premises and a false conclusion.


Valid syllogistic forms

In syllogistic logic, there are 256 possible ways to construct
categorical syllogism A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true. ...
s using the A, E, I, and O statement forms in the
square of opposition In term logic (a branch of philosophical logic), the square of opposition is a diagram representing the relations between the four basic categorical propositions. The origin of the square can be traced back to Aristotle's tractate ''On Interpr ...
. Of the 256, only 24 are valid forms. Of the 24 valid forms, 15 are unconditionally valid, and 9 are conditionally valid.


Unconditionally valid


Conditionally valid


Valid propositional forms

The following is a list of some common valid argument forms in propositional logic. It is nowhere near exhaustive, and gives only a few examples of the better known valid argument forms.


Modus ponens

One valid argument form is known as
modus ponens In propositional logic, ''modus ponens'' (; MP), also known as ''modus ponendo ponens'' (Latin for "method of putting by placing") or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. It ...
, not to be mistaken with
modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "method of removing by taking away") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens'' ...
, which is another valid argument form that has a like-sounding name and structure. Modus ponens (sometimes abbreviated as MP) says that if one thing is true, then another will be. It then states that the first is true. The conclusion is that the second thing is true. It is shown below in logical form. :If A, then B :A :Therefore B Before being put into logical form the above statement could have been something like below. :If Kelly does not finish his homework, he will not go to class :Kelly did not finish his homework :Therefore, Kelly will not go to class The first two statements are the premises while the third is the conclusion derived from them.


Modus tollens

Another form of argument is known as
modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "method of removing by taking away") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens'' ...
(commonly abbreviated MT). In this form, you start with the same first premise as with modus ponens. However, the second part of the premise is denied, leading to the conclusion that the first part of the premise should be denied as well. It is shown below in logical form. :If A, then B :Not B :Therefore not A. When modus tollens is used with actual content, it looks like below. :If the Saints win the Super Bowl, there will be a party in New Orleans that night :There was no party in New Orleans that night :Therefore, the Saints did not win the Super Bowl


Hypothetical syllogism

Much like modus ponens and modus tollens,
hypothetical syllogism In classical logic, a hypothetical syllogism is a valid argument form, a syllogism with a conditional statement for one or both of its premises. An example in English: :If I do not wake up, then I cannot go to work. :If I cannot go to work, then ...
(sometimes abbreviated as HS) contains two premises and a conclusion. It is, however, slightly more complicated than the first two. In short, it states that if one thing happens, another will as well. If that second thing happens, a third will follow it. Therefore, if the first thing happens, it is inevitable that the third will too. It is shown below in logical form. :If A, then B :If B, then C :Therefore if A, then C When put into words it looks like below. :If it rains today, I will wear my rain jacket :If I wear my rain jacket, I will keep dry :Therefore if it rains today, I will keep dry


Disjunctive syllogism

Disjunctive syllogism In classical logic, disjunctive syllogism (historically known as ''modus tollendo ponens'' (MTP), Latin for "mode that affirms by denying") is a valid argument form which is a syllogism having a disjunctive statement for one of its premises. ...
(sometimes abbreviated DS) has one of the same characteristics as modus tollens in that it contains a premise, then in a second premise it denies a statement, leading to the conclusion. In Disjunctive Syllogism, the first premise establishes two options. The second takes one away, so the conclusion states that the remaining one must be true. It is shown below in logical form. :Either A or B :Not A :Therefore B When A and B are replaced with real life examples it looks like below. :Either you will see Joe in class today or he will oversleep :You did not see Joe in class today :Therefore Joe overslept Disjunctive syllogism takes two options and narrows it down to one.


Constructive dilemma

Another valid form of argument is known as
constructive dilemma Constructive dilemmaCopi and Cohen is a valid rule of inference of propositional logic. It is the inference that, if ''P'' implies ''Q'' and ''R'' implies ''S'' and either ''P'' or ''R'' is true, then either ''Q or S'' has to be true. In sum, i ...
or sometimes just 'dilemma'. It does not leave the user with one statement alone at the end of the argument, instead, it gives an option of two different statements. The first premise gives an option of two different statements. Then it states that if the first one happens, there will be a particular outcome and if the second happens, there will be a separate outcome. The conclusion is that either the first outcome or the second outcome will happen. The criticism with this form is that it does not give a definitive conclusion; just a statement of possibilities. When it is written in argument form it looks like below. :Either A or B :If A then C :If B then D :Therefore either C or D When content is inserted in place of the letters, it looks like below. :Bill will either take the stairs or the elevator to his room :If he takes the stairs, he will be tired when he gets to his room :If he takes the elevator, he will miss the start of the football game on TV :Therefore Bill will either be tired when he gets to his room or he will miss the start of the football game There is a slightly different version of dilemma that uses negation rather than affirming something known as
destructive dilemma Destructive dilemmaMoore and Parker is the name of a valid rule of inference of propositional logic. It is the inference that, if ''P'' implies ''Q'' and ''R'' implies ''S'' and either ''Q'' is false or ''S'' is false, then either ''P'' or ''R' ...
. When put in argumentative form it looks like below. :If A then C :If B then D :Not C or not D :Therefore not A or not B


References

{{reflist Rules of inference Valid argument forms Arguments