HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics,
forcing Forcing may refer to: Mathematics and science * Forcing (mathematics), a technique for obtaining independence proofs for set theory *Forcing (recursion theory), a modification of Paul Cohen's original set theoretic technique of forcing to deal with ...
is a method of constructing new models ''M'' 'G''of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concer ...
by adding a generic subset ''G'' of a
poset In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binary r ...
''P'' to a model ''M''. The poset ''P'' used will determine what statements hold in the new universe (the 'extension'); to force a statement of interest thus requires construction of a suitable ''P''. This article lists some of the posets ''P'' that have been used in this construction.


Notation

*''P'' is a poset with order < *''V'' is the universe of all sets *''M'' is a countable transitive model of set theory *''G'' is a generic subset of ''P'' over ''M''.


Definitions

*''P'' satisfies the
countable chain condition In order theory, a partially ordered set ''X'' is said to satisfy the countable chain condition, or to be ccc, if every strong antichain in ''X'' is countable. Overview There are really two conditions: the ''upwards'' and ''downwards'' countable ...
if every antichain in ''P'' is at most countable. This implies that ''V'' and ''V'' 'G''have the same cardinals (and the same cofinalities). *A subset ''D'' of ''P'' is called dense if for every there is some with . *A filter on ''P'' is a nonempty subset ''F'' of ''P'' such that if and then , and if and then there is some with and . *A subset ''G'' of ''P'' is called generic over ''M'' if it is a filter that meets every dense subset of ''P'' in ''M''.


Amoeba forcing

Amoeba forcing is forcing with the amoeba order, and adds a measure 1 set of random reals.


Cohen forcing

In Cohen forcing (named after Paul Cohen) ''P'' is the set of functions from a finite subset of ω2 × ω to and if . This poset satisfies the countable chain condition. Forcing with this poset adds ω2 distinct reals to the model; this was the poset used by Cohen in his original proof of the independence of the continuum hypothesis. More generally, one can replace ω2 by any cardinal κ so construct a model where the continuum has size at least κ. Here, there is no restriction. If κ has cofinality ω, the reals end up bigger than κ.


Grigorieff forcing

Grigorieff forcing (after Serge Grigorieff) destroys a free
ultrafilter In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a maximal filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter o ...
on ω.


Hechler forcing

Hechler forcing (after Stephen Herman Hechler) is used to show that Martin's axiom implies that every family of less than ''c'' functions from ω to ω is eventually dominated by some such function. ''P'' is the set of pairs where ''s'' is a finite sequence of natural numbers (considered as functions from a finite ordinal to ω) and ''E'' is a finite subset of some fixed set ''G'' of functions from ω to ω. The element (''s'', ''E'') is stronger than if ''t'' is contained in ''s'', ''F'' is contained in ''E'', and if ''k'' is in the domain of ''s'' but not of ''t'' then for all ''h'' in ''F''.


Jockusch–Soare forcing

Forcing with \Pi^0_1 classes was invented by
Robert Soare Robert Irving Soare is an American mathematician. He is the Paul Snowden Russell Distinguished Service Professor of Mathematics and Computer Science at the University of Chicago, where he has been on the faculty since 1967. He proved, together ...
and
Carl Jockusch Carl Groos Jockusch Jr. (born July 13, 1941, in San Antonio, Texas) is an American mathematician. He graduated from Alamo Heights High School in 1959, attended Vanderbilt University in Nashville, Tennessee, and transferred to Swarthmore Colleg ...
to prove, among other results, the
low basis theorem The low basis theorem is one of several basis theorems in computability theory, each of which showing that, given an infinite subtree of the binary tree 2^, it is possible to find an infinite path through the tree with particular computability prop ...
. Here ''P'' is the set of nonempty \Pi^0_1 subsets of 2^ (meaning the sets of paths through infinite, computable
subtrees In computer science, a tree is a widely used abstract data type that represents a hierarchical tree structure with a set of connected nodes. Each node in the tree can be connected to many children (depending on the type of tree), but must be con ...
of 2^), ordered by inclusion.


Iterated forcing

Iterated forcing with finite supports was introduced by
Solovay Robert Martin Solovay (born December 15, 1938) is an American mathematician specializing in set theory. Biography Solovay earned his Ph.D. from the University of Chicago in 1964 under the direction of Saunders Mac Lane, with a dissertation ...
and Tennenbaum to show the consistency of Suslin's hypothesis. Easton introduced another type of iterated forcing to determine the possible values of the continuum function at regular cardinals. Iterated forcing with countable support was investigated by
Laver Laver may refer to: * Laver (surname), a list of people with the name * Laver (ghost town), Sweden * Green laver, a type of edible green seaweed used to make laverbread * River Laver, a river in North Yorkshire, England * Lavatorium, a washing fa ...
in his proof of the consistency of Borel's conjecture,
Baumgartner Baumgartner (also Baumgärtner, Baumgardner, Bumgardner, Bumgartner or Bumgarner) is a surname of German origin, literally meaning " Tree Gardener". It may refer to: ;Baumgartner surname * Ann Baumgartner (1918–2008), first American female jet p ...
, who introduced Axiom A forcing, and
Shelah Shelah may refer to: * Shelah (son of Judah), a son of Judah according to the Bible * Shelah (name), a Hebrew personal name * Shlach, the 37th weekly Torah portion (parshah) in the annual Jewish cycle of Torah reading * Salih, a prophet described ...
, who introduced proper forcing. Revised countable support iteration was introduced by
Shelah Shelah may refer to: * Shelah (son of Judah), a son of Judah according to the Bible * Shelah (name), a Hebrew personal name * Shlach, the 37th weekly Torah portion (parshah) in the annual Jewish cycle of Torah reading * Salih, a prophet described ...
to handle semi-proper forcings, such as Prikry forcing, and generalizations, notably including Namba forcing.


Laver forcing

Laver forcing was used by
Laver Laver may refer to: * Laver (surname), a list of people with the name * Laver (ghost town), Sweden * Green laver, a type of edible green seaweed used to make laverbread * River Laver, a river in North Yorkshire, England * Lavatorium, a washing fa ...
to show that Borel's conjecture, which says that all
strong measure zero set In mathematical analysis, a strong measure zero set is a subset ''A'' of the real line with the following property: :for every sequence (ε''n'') of positive reals there exists a sequence (''In'') of intervals such that , ''I'n'', < ε''n' ...
s are countable, is consistent with ZFC. (Borel's conjecture is not consistent with the continuum hypothesis.) *''P'' is the set of Laver trees, ordered by inclusion. A Laver tree ''p'' is a subset of the finite sequences of natural numbers such that * ''p'' is a tree: ''p'' contains any initial sequence of any element of ''p'', equivalently stated as ''p'' is closed under initial segments * ''p'' has a stem: a maximal node such that or for all ''t'' in ''p'', *If and then ''t'' has an infinite number of immediate successors ''tn'' in ''p'' for . If ''G'' is generic for , then the real , called a ''Laver-real'', uniquely determines ''G''. Laver forcing satisfies the
Laver property In mathematical set theory, the Laver property holds between two models if they are not "too dissimilar", in the following sense. For M and N transitive models of set theory, N is said to have the Laver property over M if and only if for every func ...
.


Levy collapsing

These posets will collapse various cardinals, in other words force them to be equal in size to smaller cardinals. *Collapsing a cardinal to ω: ''P'' is the set of all finite sequences of ordinals less than a given cardinal λ. If λ is uncountable then forcing with this poset collapses λ to ω. *Collapsing a cardinal to another: ''P'' is the set of all functions from a subset of κ of cardinality less than κ to λ (for fixed cardinals κ and λ). Forcing with this poset collapses λ down to κ. *Levy collapsing: If κ is regular and λ is inaccessible, then ''P'' is the set of functions ''p'' on subsets of with domain of size less than κ and for every in the domain of ''p''. This poset collapses all cardinals less than λ onto κ, but keeps λ as the successor to κ. Levy collapsing is named for
Azriel Levy Azriel, Asriel or Ezriel may refer to: People * Azriel of Gerona (c. 1160–c. 1238), Catalan kabbalist * Azriel Hildesheimer (1820–1899), German rabbi * Azriel Rabinowitz (1905–1941), Lithuanian rabbi and Holocaust victim * Azriel Rosenfeld ...
.


Magidor forcing

Amongst many forcing notions developed by Magidor, one of the best known is a generalization of Prikry forcing used to change the cofinality of a cardinal to a given smaller regular cardinal.


Mathias forcing

*An element of ''P'' is a pair consisting of a finite set ''s'' of natural numbers and an infinite set ''A'' of natural numbers such that every element of ''s'' is less than every element of ''A''. The order is defined by : is stronger than if ''s'' is an initial segment of ''t'', ''B'' is a subset of ''A'', and ''t'' is contained in . Mathias forcing is named for
Adrian Mathias Adrian Richard David Mathias (born 12 February 1944) is a British mathematician working in set theory. The forcing notion Mathias forcing is named for him. Career Mathias was educated at Shrewsbury and Trinity College, Cambridge, where he read ...
.


Namba forcing

Namba forcing (after Kanji Namba) is used to change the cofinality of ω2 to ω without collapsing ω1. *''P'' is the set of all trees T \subseteq \omega_2^ (nonempty downward closed subsets of the set of finite sequences of ordinals less than ω2) which have the property that any ''s'' in ''T'' has an extension in ''T'' which has \aleph_2 immediate successors. ''P'' is ordered by inclusion (i.e., subtrees are stronger conditions). The intersection of all trees in the generic filter defines a countable sequence which is cofinal in ω2. Namba' forcing is the subset of ''P'' such that there is a node below which the ordering is linear and above which each node has \aleph_2 immediate successors. Magidor and
Shelah Shelah may refer to: * Shelah (son of Judah), a son of Judah according to the Bible * Shelah (name), a Hebrew personal name * Shlach, the 37th weekly Torah portion (parshah) in the annual Jewish cycle of Torah reading * Salih, a prophet described ...
proved that if CH holds then a generic object of Namba forcing does not exist in the generic extension by Namba', and vice versa.Schlindwein, C., Shelah's work on non-semiproper iterations, I, Archive for Mathematical Logic, vol. 47, no. 6, pp. 579 -- 606 (2008)


Prikry forcing

In Prikry forcing (after Karel Prikrý) ''P'' is the set of pairs where ''s'' is a finite subset of a fixed measurable cardinal κ, and ''A'' is an element of a fixed normal measure ''D'' on κ. A condition is stronger than if ''t'' is an initial segment of ''s'', ''A'' is contained in ''B'', and ''s'' is contained in . This forcing notion can be used to change to cofinality of κ while preserving all cardinals.


Product forcing

Taking a product of forcing conditions is a way of simultaneously forcing all the conditions. *Finite products: If ''P'' and ''Q'' are posets, the product poset has the partial order defined by if and . *Infinite products: The product of a set of posets , each with a largest element 1 is the set of functions ''p'' on ''I'' with and such that for all but a finite number of ''i''. The order is given by if for all ''i''. *The Easton product (after William Bigelow Easton) of a set of posets , where ''I'' is a set of cardinals is the set of functions ''p'' on ''I'' with and such that for every regular cardinal γ the number of elements α of γ with is less than γ.


Radin forcing

Radin forcing (after Lon Berk Radin), a technically involved generalization of Magidor forcing, adds a closed, unbounded subset to some regular cardinal λ. If λ is a sufficiently large cardinal, then the forcing keeps λ regular,
measurable In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures (length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as mass and probability of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many simila ...
, supercompact, etc.


Random forcing

*''P'' is the set of Borel subsets of ,1of positive measure, where ''p'' is called stronger than ''q'' if it is contained in ''q''. The generic set ''G'' then encodes a "random real": the unique real ''x''''G'' in all rational intervals such that is in ''G''. This real is "random" in the sense that if ''X'' is any subset of of measure 1, lying in ''V'', then .


Sacks forcing

*''P'' is the set of all perfect trees contained in the set of finite sequences. (A tree ''T'' is a set of finite sequences containing all initial segments of its members, and is called perfect if for any element ''t'' of ''T'' there is a segment ''s'' extending ''t'' so that both ''s''0 and ''s''1 are in ''T''.) A tree ''p'' is stronger than ''q'' if ''p'' is contained in ''q''. Forcing with perfect trees was used by Gerald Enoch Sacks to produce a real ''a'' with minimal degree of constructibility. Sacks forcing has the
Sacks property In mathematical set theory, the Sacks property holds between two models of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory if they are not "too dissimilar" in the following sense. For M and N transitive models of set theory, N is said to have the Sacks property ove ...
.


Shooting a fast club

For ''S'' a stationary subset of \omega_1 we set P=\, ordered by \langle \sigma',C'\rangle\leq\langle\sigma, C\rangle iff \sigma' end-extends \sigma and C'\subseteq C and \sigma'\subseteq\sigma\cup C. In V /math>, we have that \bigcup\ is a closed unbounded subset of ''S'' almost contained in each club set in ''V''. \aleph_1 is preserved. This method was introduced by
Ronald Jensen Ronald Björn Jensen (born April 1, 1936) is an American mathematician who lives in Germany, primarily known for his work in mathematical logic and set theory. Career Jensen completed a BA in economics at American University in 1959, and a Ph.D. ...
in order to show the consistency of the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent ...
and the
Suslin hypothesis In mathematics, Suslin's problem is a question about totally ordered sets posed by and published posthumously. It has been shown to be independent of the standard axiomatic system of set theory known as ZFC: showed that the statement can neither ...
.


Shooting a club with countable conditions

For ''S'' a stationary subset of \omega_1 we set ''P'' equal to the set of closed countable sequences from ''S''. In V /math>, we have that \bigcup G is a closed unbounded subset of ''S'' and \aleph_1 is preserved, and if CH holds then all cardinals are preserved.


Shooting a club with finite conditions

For ''S'' a stationary subset of \omega_1 we set ''P'' equal to the set of finite sets of pairs of countable ordinals, such that if p\in P and \langle\alpha,\beta\rangle\in p then \alpha\leq\beta and \alpha\in S, and whenever \langle\alpha,\beta\rangle and \langle\gamma,\delta\rangle are distinct elements of ''p'' then either \beta<\gamma or \delta<\alpha. ''P'' is ordered by reverse inclusion. In V /math>, we have that \ is a closed unbounded subset of ''S'' and all cardinals are preserved.


Silver forcing

Silver forcing (after Jack Howard Silver) is the set of all those partial functions from the natural numbers into whose domain is coinfinite; or equivalently the set of all pairs , where ''A'' is a subset of the natural numbers with infinite complement, and ''p'' is a function from ''A'' into a fixed 2-element set. A condition ''q'' is stronger than a condition ''p'' if ''q'' extends ''p''. Silver forcing satisfies Fusion, the
Sacks property In mathematical set theory, the Sacks property holds between two models of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory if they are not "too dissimilar" in the following sense. For M and N transitive models of set theory, N is said to have the Sacks property ove ...
, and is minimal with respect to reals (but not minimal).


Vopěnka forcing

Vopěnka forcing (after Petr Vopěnka) is used to generically add a set A of ordinals to . Define first P' as the set of all non-empty \text subsets of the power set \mathcal(\alpha) of \alpha, where A\subseteq\alpha, ordered by inclusion: p\leq q iff p\subseteq q. Each condition p\in P' can be represented by a tuple (\beta,\gamma,\varphi) where x\in p\Leftrightarrow V_\beta\models\varphi(\gamma,x), for all x\subseteq\alpha. The translation between p and its least representation is \text, and hence P' is isomorphic to a poset P\in\text (the conditions being the minimal representations of elements of P'). This poset is the Vopenka forcing for subsets of \alpha. Defining G_A as the set of all representations for elements p\in P' such that A\in p, then G_A is \text-generic and A\in\text _A/math>.


References

* * *{{citation , last=Kunen , first=Kenneth , authorlink=Kenneth Kunen , title=Set theory , zbl=1262.03001 , series=Studies in Logic , volume=34 , location=London , publisher=College Publications , isbn=978-1-84890-050-9 , year=2011


External links

*A.Miller (2009)
''Forcing Tidbits.''
Forcing (mathematics)