HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, specifically in
axiomatic set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
, a Hartogs number is an
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
associated with a set. In particular, if ''X'' is any
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
, then the Hartogs number of ''X'' is the least ordinal α such that there is no injection from α into ''X''. If ''X'' can be
well-ordered In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set ''S'' is a total order on ''S'' with the property that every non-empty subset of ''S'' has a least element in this ordering. The set ''S'' together with the well-or ...
then the
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. ...
of α is a minimal cardinal greater than that of ''X''. If ''X'' cannot be well-ordered then there cannot be an injection from ''X'' to α. However, the cardinal number of α is still a minimal cardinal ''not less than or equal to'' the cardinality of ''X''. (If we restrict to cardinal numbers of well-orderable sets then that of α is the smallest that is not not less than or equal to that of ''X''.) The map taking ''X'' to α is sometimes called Hartogs's function. This mapping is used to construct the aleph numbers, which are all the cardinal numbers of infinite well-orderable sets. The existence of the Hartogs number was proved by Friedrich Hartogs in 1915, using
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such ...
alone (that is, without using the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
).


Hartogs's theorem

Hartogs's theorem states that for any set ''X'', there exists an ordinal α such that , \alpha, \not \le , X, ; that is, such that there is no injection from α to ''X''. As ordinals are well-ordered, this immediately implies the existence of a Hartogs number for any set ''X''. Furthermore, the proof is constructive and yields the Hartogs number of ''X''.


Proof

See . Let \alpha = \ be the
class Class or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used differently ...
of all
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s ''β'' for which an
injective function In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositi ...
exists from ''β'' into ''X''. First, we verify that ''α'' is a set. #''X'' × ''X'' is a set, as can be seen in Axiom of power set. # The
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
of ''X'' × ''X'' is a set, by the axiom of power set. # The class ''W'' of all reflexive well-orderings of subsets of ''X'' is a definable subclass of the preceding set, so it is a set by the axiom schema of separation. # The class of all
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y suc ...
s of well-orderings in ''W'' is a set by the axiom schema of replacement, as #::(Domain(''w''), ''w'') \cong (''β'', ≤) #:can be described by a simple formula. But this last set is exactly ''α''. Now, because a transitive set of ordinals is again an ordinal, ''α'' is an ordinal. Furthermore, there is no injection from ''α'' into ''X'', because if there were, then we would get the contradiction that ''α'' ∈ ''α''. And finally, ''α'' is the least such ordinal with no injection into ''X''. This is true because, since ''α'' is an ordinal, for any ''β'' < ''α'', ''β'' ∈ ''α'' so there is an injection from ''β'' into ''X''.


Historic remark

In 1915, Hartogs could use neither von Neumann-ordinals nor the
replacement axiom In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
, and so his result is one of Zermelo set theory and looks rather different from the modern exposition above. Instead, he considered the set of isomorphism classes of well-ordered subsets of ''X'' and the relation in which the class of ''A'' precedes that of ''B'' if ''A'' is
isomorphic In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between them. The word i ...
with a proper initial segment of ''B''. Hartogs showed this to be a well-ordering greater than any well-ordered subset of ''X''. (This must have been historically the first genuine construction of an uncountable well-ordering.) However, the main purpose of his contribution was to show that trichotomy for cardinal numbers implies the (then 11 year old)
well-ordering theorem In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set ''X'' is ''well-ordered'' by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of ''X'' has a least element under the orde ...
(and, hence, the axiom of choice).


See also

* Successor cardinal * Aleph number


References

* * * * {{cite web , title=Axiomatic set theory , work=Course Notes , author=Charles Morgan , publisher=University of Bristol , url=http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~ucahcjm/ast/ast_notes_4.pdf , access-date =2010-04-10 Set theory Cardinal numbers