Forcing (computability)
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Forcing in
computability theory Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since ex ...
is a modification of Paul Cohen's original
set-theoretic Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathematics – is mostly ...
technique of forcing to deal with computability concerns. Conceptually the two techniques are quite similar: in both one attempts to build generic objects (intuitively objects that are somehow 'typical') by meeting
dense set In topology and related areas of mathematics, a subset ''A'' of a topological space ''X'' is said to be dense in ''X'' if every point of ''X'' either belongs to ''A'' or else is arbitrarily "close" to a member of ''A'' — for instance, the ...
s. Both techniques are described as a relation (customarily denoted \Vdash) between 'conditions' and sentences. However, where set-theoretic forcing is usually interested in creating objects that meet every dense set of conditions in the ground model, computability-theoretic forcing only aims to meet dense sets that are arithmetically or hyperarithmetically definable. Therefore, some of the more difficult machinery used in set-theoretic forcing can be eliminated or substantially simplified when defining forcing in computability. But while the machinery may be somewhat different, computability-theoretic and set-theoretic forcing are properly regarded as an application of the same technique to different classes of formulas.


Terminology

In this article we use the following terminology. ;real: an element of 2^\omega. In other words, a function that maps each integer to either 0 or 1. ;string: an element of 2^. In other words, a finite approximation to a real. ;notion of forcing: A notion of forcing is a set P and a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable ...
on P, \succ_ with a ''greatest element'' 0_. ;condition: An element in a notion of forcing. We say a condition p is stronger than a condition q just when q \succ_P p. ;compatible conditions: Given conditions p,q say that p and q are compatible if there is a condition r such that with respect to r, both p and q can be simultaneously satisfied if they are true or allowed to coexist. ;p\mid q means p and q are incompatible. ;Filter : A subset F of a notion of forcing P is a filter if p,q \in F \implies p \nmid q, and p \in F \land q \succ_P p \implies q \in F. In other words, a filter is a compatible set of conditions closed under weakening of conditions. ;Ultrafilter: A maximal filter, i.e., F is an ultrafilter if F is a filter and there is no filter F' properly containing F. ;Cohen forcing: The notion of forcing C where conditions are elements of 2^ and (\tau \succ_C \sigma \iff \sigma \supset \tau) Note that for Cohen forcing \succ_ is the reverse of the containment relation. This leads to an unfortunate notational confusion where some computability theorists reverse the direction of the forcing partial order (exchanging \succ_P with \prec_P, which is more natural for Cohen forcing, but is at odds with the notation used in set theory).


Generic objects

The intuition behind forcing is that our conditions are finite approximations to some object we wish to build and that \sigma is stronger than \tau when \sigma agrees with everything \tau says about the object we are building and adds some information of its own. For instance in Cohen forcing the conditions can be viewed as finite approximations to a real and if \tau \succ_C \sigma then \sigma tells us the value of the real at more places. In a moment we will define a relation \sigma \Vdash_P \psi (read \sigma forces \psi) that holds between conditions (elements of P) and sentences, but first we need to explain the
language Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
that \psi is a sentence for. However, forcing is a technique, not a definition, and the language for \psi will depend on the application one has in mind and the choice of P. The idea is that our language should express facts about the object we wish to build with our forcing construction.


Forcing relation

The forcing relation \Vdash was developed by
Paul Cohen Paul Joseph Cohen (April 2, 1934 – March 23, 2007) was an American mathematician, best known for his proofs that the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice are independent from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, for which he was awarded a F ...
, who introduced forcing as a technique for proving the independence of certain statements from the standard axioms of set theory, particularly the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
(CH). The notation V \Vdash \phi is used to express that a particular condition or generic set forces a certain proposition or formula \phi to be true in the resulting forcing extension. Here's V represents the original universe of sets (the ground model), \Vdash denotes the forcing relation, and \phi is a statement in set theory. When V \Vdash \phi, it means that in a suitable forcing extension, the statement \phi will be true.


References

* *{{Cite book , last=Odifreddi , first=Piergiorgio , author-link=Piergiorgio Odifreddi , year=1999 , title=Classical recursion theory. Vol. II , publisher=North-Holland Publishing Company , location=Amsterdam , series=Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics , isbn=978-0-444-50205-6 , mr=1718169 , volume=143 Computability theory