Falsifiability
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Falsifiability () (or refutability) is a standard of evaluation of scientific theories and hypotheses. A
hypothesis A hypothesis (: hypotheses) is a proposed explanation for a phenomenon. A scientific hypothesis must be based on observations and make a testable and reproducible prediction about reality, in a process beginning with an educated guess o ...
is falsifiable if it belongs to a language or logical structure capable of describing an
empirical observation Empirical evidence is evidence obtained through sense experience or experimental procedure. It is of central importance to the sciences and plays a role in various other fields, like epistemology and law. There is no general agreement on how the ...
that contradicts it. It was introduced by the
philosopher of science Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
Karl Popper Sir Karl Raimund Popper (28 July 1902 – 17 September 1994) was an Austrian–British philosopher, academic and social commentator. One of the 20th century's most influential philosophers of science, Popper is known for his rejection of the ...
in his book ''
The Logic of Scientific Discovery ''The Logic of Scientific Discovery'' is a 1959 book about the philosophy of science by the philosopher Karl Popper. Popper rewrote his book in English from the 1934 (imprint '1935') German original, titled ''Logik der Forschung. Zur Erkenntnisth ...
'' (1934). Popper emphasized that the contradiction is to be found in the logical structure alone, without having to worry about methodological considerations external to this structure. He proposed falsifiability as the cornerstone solution to both the
problem of induction The problem of induction is a philosophical problem that questions the rationality of predictions about unobserved things based on previous observations. These inferences from the observed to the unobserved are known as "inductive inferences" ...
and the
problem of demarcation In philosophy of science and epistemology, the demarcation problem is the question of how to distinguish between science and non-science. It also examines the boundaries between science, pseudoscience and other products of human activity, like ar ...
. Popper also emphasized the related asymmetry created by the relation of a
universal law In law and ethics, universal law or universal principle refers to concepts of legal legitimacy actions, whereby those principles and rules for governing human beings' conduct which are most universal in their acceptability, their applicability, ...
with basic observation statements and contrasted falsifiability with the intuitively similar concept of ''verifiability'' that was then current in the philosophical discipline of
logical positivism Logical positivism, also known as logical empiricism or neo-positivism, was a philosophical movement, in the empiricist tradition, that sought to formulate a scientific philosophy in which philosophical discourse would be, in the perception of ...
. He argued that the only way to verify a claim such as "All swans are white" would be if one could empirically observe all swans, which is not possible. On the other hand, the observation of a single black swan is enough to refute this claim. This asymmetry can only be seen clearly when methodological falsification issues are put aside. Otherwise, a stated observation of one or even more black swans constitute at best a problematic refutation of the claim. Accordingly, to be rigorous, falsifiability is a logical criterion within an empirical language that is accepted by convention and allows these methodological considerations to be avoided. Only then the asymmetry and falsifiability are rigorous. Popper argued that it should not be conflated with falsificationism, which is a methodological approach where scientists actively try to find evidence to disprove theories. Falsifiability is distinct from Lakatos' falsificationism. Its purpose is to make theory
predictive A prediction (Latin ''præ-'', "before," and ''dictum'', "something said") or forecast is a statement about a future event or about future data. Predictions are often, but not always, based upon experience or knowledge of forecasters. There i ...
,
testable Testability is a primary aspect of science and the scientific method. There are two components to testability: #Falsifiability or defeasibility, which means that counterexamples to the hypothesis are logically possible. #The practical feasibilit ...
and useful in practice. By contrast, the
Duhem–Quine thesis In philosophy of science, the Duhem–Quine thesis, also called the Duhem–Quine problem, says that unambiguous falsifications of a scientific hypothesis are impossible, because an empirical test of the hypothesis requires one or more back ...
says that definitive experimental falsifications are impossible and that no scientific hypothesis is by itself capable of making predictions, because an
empirical Empirical evidence is evidence obtained through sense experience or experimental procedure. It is of central importance to the sciences and plays a role in various other fields, like epistemology and law. There is no general agreement on how t ...
test of the hypothesis requires background assumptions, which acceptations are methodological decisions in Lakatos' falsicationism. Popper's response was that falsifiability is a logical criterion. Experimental research has the Duhem problem and other problems, such as the problem of induction, but, according to Popper, logical induction is a fallacy and statistical tests, which are possible only when a theory is falsifiable, are useful within a critical discussion. Popper's distinction between logic and methodology has not allowed falsifiability to escape some criticisms aimed at methodology. For example, Popper's rejection of Marxism as unscientific because of its resistance to negative evidence is a methodological position, but the problems with this position are nevertheless presented as a limitation of falsifiability. Others, despite the unsuccessful proposals of
Russell Russell may refer to: People * Russell (given name) * Russell (surname) * Lady Russell (disambiguation) * Lord Russell (disambiguation) ** Bertrand Russell *Justice Russell (disambiguation) Places *Russell Island (disambiguation) *Mount Russel ...
, the
Vienna Circle The Vienna Circle () of logical empiricism was a group of elite philosophers and scientists drawn from the natural and social sciences, logic and mathematics who met regularly from 1924 to 1936 at the University of Vienna, chaired by Moritz Sc ...
, Lakatos, and others to establish a rigorous way of justifying scientific theories or research programs and thus demarcating them from
non-science A non-science is an area of study that is not scientific, especially one that is not a natural science or a social science that is an object of scientific inquiry. In this model, history, art, and religion are all examples of non-sciences. Clas ...
and
pseudoscience Pseudoscience consists of statements, beliefs, or practices that claim to be both scientific and factual but are incompatible with the scientific method. Pseudoscience is often characterized by contradictory, exaggerated or unfalsifiable cl ...
, criticize falsifiability for not following a similar proposal and for supporting instead only a methodology based on critical discussion. As a key notion in the separation of science from non-science and pseudoscience, falsifiability has featured prominently in many controversies and applications, used as
legal precedent Precedent is a judicial decision that serves as an authority for courts when deciding subsequent identical or similar cases. Fundamental to common law legal systems, precedent operates under the principle of ''stare decisis'' ("to stand by thin ...
.


Induction and demarcation

One concern about the
scientific method The scientific method is an Empirical evidence, empirical method for acquiring knowledge that has been referred to while doing science since at least the 17th century. Historically, it was developed through the centuries from the ancient and ...
is how to move from
observation Observation in the natural sciences is an act or instance of noticing or perceiving and the acquisition of information from a primary source. In living beings, observation employs the senses. In science, observation can also involve the percep ...
s to scientific laws. This is the problem of induction. Considering the hypothesis that all swans are white, given an observation of a white swan, there is no logical path from "here is a white swan" to "all swans are white"; doing so would involve a
logical fallacy In logic and philosophy, a formal fallacy is a pattern of reasoning rendered invalid by a flaw in its logical structure. Propositional logic, for example, is concerned with the meanings of sentences and the relationships between them. It focuses ...
such as, for example,
affirming the consequent In propositional logic, affirming the consequent (also known as converse error, fallacy of the converse, or confusion of necessity and sufficiency) is a formal fallacy (or an invalid form of argument) that is committed when, in the context of a ...
. Popper's idea to solve this problem was that while it is impossible to verify that every swan is white, finding a single black swan shows that ''not'' every swan is white. Such falsification uses the valid inference ''
modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "mode that by denying denies") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens'' is a m ...
'': if, from a law L, Q can be logically deduced, but \neg Q is observed, L is false. Thus, given L = "all swans are white", Q = "the specific swan here is white", but if what is observed is \neg Q = "an observed swan is not white", then "all swans are white" is false. More precisely, the deducible statement Q can be broken into an initial condition and a prediction as in C \Rightarrow P in which C = "the thing here is a swan" and P = "the thing here is a white swan". If what is observed is C being true while P is false (formally, C \wedge \neg P), the law is false by modus tollens. Popper claimed that induction is not needed in science, that is, he rejected that we learn by the repetition of observations and considered that logical induction was a fallacy. Instead, laws are conjectured in a non-logical manner on the basis of expectations and predispositions and trials continue as long as there are problems. This led Popper's student and collaborator David Miller to write "the mission is to classify truths, not to certify them". In contrast, the
logical empiricism Logical positivism, also known as logical empiricism or neo-positivism, was a philosophical movement, in the empiricist tradition, that sought to formulate a scientific philosophy in which philosophical discourse would be, in the perception of ...
movement, led by philosophers such as
Moritz Schlick Friedrich Albert Moritz Schlick (; ; 14 April 1882 – 22 June 1936) was a German philosopher, physicist, and the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna Circle. He was murdered by a former student, Johann Nelböck, in 1936. Early ...
,
Rudolf Carnap Rudolf Carnap (; ; 18 May 1891 – 14 September 1970) was a German-language philosopher who was active in Europe before 1935 and in the United States thereafter. He was a major member of the Vienna Circle and an advocate of logical positivism. ...
,
Otto Neurath Otto Karl Wilhelm Neurath (; ; 10 December 1882 – 22 December 1945) was an Austrian-born philosopher of science, sociologist, and political economist. He was also the inventor of the ISOTYPE method of pictorial statistics and an innovator in ...
, and
A. J. Ayer Sir Alfred Jules "Freddie" Ayer ( ; 29 October 1910 – 27 June 1989) was an English philosopher known for his promotion of logical positivism, particularly in his books '' Language, Truth, and Logic'' (1936) and ''The Problem of Knowledge'' (1 ...
, wanted to formalize the idea that, for a law to be scientific, it must be possible to argue on the basis of observations in favor of its truth or falsity. No consensus emerged about how to achieve that, but the thought expressed by Mach's dictum that "where neither confirmation nor refutation is possible, science is not concerned" was accepted as a scientific precept. Popper said that a demarcation criterion for the laws of science was possible, but that what matters is the logical possibility of falsification of these laws, which is falsifiability. He cited his encounter with
psychoanalysis PsychoanalysisFrom Greek language, Greek: and is a set of theories and techniques of research to discover unconscious mind, unconscious processes and their influence on conscious mind, conscious thought, emotion and behaviour. Based on The Inte ...
in the 1910s, especially with
Alfred Adler Alfred Adler ( ; ; 7 February 1870 – 28 May 1937) was an Austrian medical doctor, psychotherapist, and founder of the school of individual psychology. His emphasis on the importance of feelings of belonging, relationships within the family, a ...
. It did not matter what observation was presented, psychoanalysis could explain it. The reason it could explain everything is that it did not exclude anything. Popper claimed that this was a failure, because it meant that the criterion could not lead to a prediction. From a logical standpoint, observations that do not contradict a law does not mean that the law is true. A verification has no value in itself. But, if a hypothesis makes risky predictions and these are corroborated, Popper stated, that was a reason to prefer this hypothesis over others that makes less risky predictions or no predictions at all. In the definition of falsifiability, contradictions with observations are not used to support falsifications, but for logical "falsifications" that show that the law makes risky predictions. Popper said that some philosophers of the
Vienna Circle The Vienna Circle () of logical empiricism was a group of elite philosophers and scientists drawn from the natural and social sciences, logic and mathematics who met regularly from 1924 to 1936 at the University of Vienna, chaired by Moritz Sc ...
had conflated two problems, that of meaning and that of demarcation, and had proposed in
verificationism Verificationism, also known as the verification principle or the verifiability criterion of meaning, is a doctrine in philosophy which asserts that a statement is meaningful only if it is either empirically verifiable (can be confirmed through the ...
a single solution to both: a statement that could not be verified was considered meaningless. Popper instead said that meaningful non-scientific theories exist, and that, accordingly, a criterion of meaningfulness does not coincide with a criterion of demarcation.


Hume's problem

The problem of induction is often called Hume's problem.
David Hume David Hume (; born David Home; – 25 August 1776) was a Scottish philosopher, historian, economist, and essayist who was best known for his highly influential system of empiricism, philosophical scepticism and metaphysical naturalism. Beg ...
studied how human beings obtain new knowledge that goes beyond known laws and observations, including how to discover new laws. He understood that deductive logic could not explain this learning process and argued in favour of a mental or psychological process of learning that would not require deductive logic. He argued that this learning process cannot be justified by any general rules, deductive or not. Popper accepted Hume's argument and therefore viewed progress in science as the result of quasi-induction, which is induction without inference rules and which he also called the "path of science". Philip N. Johnson-Laird agreed with Hume that no general method of justification for induction is possible but that induction does not require justification. Instead, these steps use patterns of induction, which are not expected to have a general justification: they may or may not be applicable depending on context. Johnson-Laird's view was that "induction is just something that animals, including human beings, do to make life possible". Popper accepted the possibility of a psychological explanation for the learning process, especially when psychology is seen as an extension of biology, but claimed that biological explanations were not within the scope of epistemology. In line with Johnson-Laird's view, Popper proposed an evolutionary mechanism to explain science's success, but he did not consider it part of his epistemology. He referred to this as psychologism. He wrote that his interest was mainly in the ''logic'' of science and that epistemology should be concerned with logical aspects only. Instead of asking why science succeeds, he considered induction pragmatically. He asked what methodology should be used to accept one among multiple hypotheses. He proposed that it be the one that was the most tested: "the one, which in the light of our ''critical discussion'', appears to be the best so far". By his own account, because only a negative approach was supported by logic, Popper adopted a negative methodology to prevent the "policy of immunizing our theories against refutation". It also supported a "dogmatic attitude" in defending theories against criticism, because this would allow the process to be more complete. This view was much criticized.


A different notion of induction

In practice, some steps based on observations can be justified under assumptions. For example, Bayesian inductive logic is justified by theorems that make explicit assumptions. These theorems are obtained with deductive logic. They are sometimes presented as supporting steps of induction, because they refer to laws of probability, even though they do not extend beyond deductive logic. This is a different notion of induction, which overlaps with deductive logic in the sense of being supported by it. Hume's argument does not reject the possibility of a general procedure that relies on hypotheses to explain the progress of science, but it says the problem of how to choose the initial hypotheses and prove their validity creates an infinite regress.


Logic of science versus applied methodology

Popper distinguished the logic of science from its applied ''methodology''. For example, the falsifiability of Newton's law of gravitation, as defined by Popper, depends purely on the logical relation it has with a statement such as "The brick fell upwards when released". A brick that falls upwards would not alone falsify Newton's law of gravitation. The capacity to verify the absence of conditions such as a hidden string attached to the brick is also needed for this state of affairs to eventually falsify Newton's law of gravitation. However, these applied methodological considerations are irrelevant in falsifiability, because it is a logical criterion. The empirical requirement on the potential falsifier, also called the material requirement, is only that it is communicable inter-subjectively. The potential falsifier is not required to actually show the law to be false. The purely logical contradiction, together with the material requirement, are sufficient. The logical part consists of theories, statements, and their logical relationship together with this material requirement, which is needed for a connection with the methodological part. The methodological part consists, in Popper's view, of informal rules, which are used to formulate hypotheses, accept observations as factual, etc. These include statistical tests: Popper is aware that observation statements are accepted with the help of statistical methods and that these involve methodological decisions. When this distinction is applied to the term "falsifiability", it corresponds to a distinction between two different meanings of the term. The same is true for the term "falsifiable". Popper said that he only uses "falsifiability" or "falsifiable" in reference to the logical side and that, when he refers to the methodological side, he speaks instead of "falsification" and its problems. Popper said that methodological problems require methodology rules. One such rule is that, refusing to go along with falsifications is equivalent to retiring from science. The logical side has no such methodological problems, in particular with regard to the falsifiability of a theory, because basic statements are not required to be possible. Methodological rules are only needed in the context of actual falsifications. So observations have two purposes. On the methodological side, observations can show that a law is false. On the logical side, observations, which are purely logical constructions, contradict a law to show its falsifiability. Unlike falsifications and free from the problems of falsification, these contradictions establish the value of the law, which may eventually be corroborated. Popper wrote that an entire literature exists because this distinction between the logical and the methodological was not observed. This survives in later literature. For example, in their 2019 article "Evidence based medicine as science", Vere and Gibson wrote " alsifiability hasbeen considered problematic because theories are not simply tested through falsification but in conjunction with auxiliary assumptions and background knowledge." According to Thornton, Popper's distinction between logic and methodology did not allow falsifiability, even when presented as a logical criterion, to escape criticism aimed at methodology. For example, the dismissal of Marxism as unscientific because it was not abandoned despite the evidence was a methodological position adopted by Popper, and problems with this position have been presented by Lakatos and others as a limitation of his criterion of demarcation.


Practical value of a logical criterion

The fact that science must be based on empirical evidence does not mean that a logical criterion fails to address the real concerns of science. As explained by Thornton, there is no methodological falsifications in the process of science except in those tests that compare the theory with factual observations, but in these tests too the procedure is mostly logical and involves observations that are only logical constructions. Popper distinguishes four different lines along which the testing of a theory could be carried out. First there is the logical comparison of deduced statements by which the internal consistency of the system is tested. Second, there is the determination whether it has the character of an empirical or scientific theory, or whether it is, for example, tautological, as required by the falsifiability criterion. Third, there is the comparison with other theories to determine whether the theory would constitute a scientific advance if not empirically rejected. Finally and most importantly, there is the testing of the theory by way of empirical applications of the conclusions which can be derived from it, which would not be possible without falsifiability. Here, too, the testing procedure turns out to require deductive logic, essentially because it is needed to properly conceive, implement, and interpret observations. The logical aspect of the criterion makes it practical, because it goes along the usual activities in science.


Basic statements

In Popper's view, observation statements can be analyzed within a logical structure independent of factual observations. The set of all purely logical observations that are considered constitutes the empirical basis. Popper calls them the basic statements or test statements. They can be used to show the falsifiability of a theory. Popper says that basic statements do not have to be possible. It is sufficient that they are accepted by convention as belonging to the empirical language, a language that "must be testable by intersubjective observation (the material requirement)". When there is a technological advance, a technology that was previously only hypothetical, for example, the use of a rocket to examine the hidden surface of the moon, might become available with all the details known. This has led to write: "a hypotheses that was first untestable may become testable later on." Formally, though, one might counter argue that it's not the same theory, because the basic statements are interpreted slightly differently with the actual details. In ''The Logic of Scientific Discovery'', Popper discusses informally which statements among those that are considered in the logical structure are basic statements. A logical structure uses universal classes to define laws. For example, in the law "all swans are white" the concept of swans is a universal class. It corresponds to a set of properties that every swan must have. It is not restricted to the swans that exist, existed or will exist. Informally, a basic statement is simply a statement that concerns only a finite number of specific instances in universal classes. In particular, an existential statement such as "there exists a black swan" is not a basic statement, because it is not specific about the instance. On the other hand, "this swan here is black" is a basic statement. Popper says that it is a singular existential statement or simply a singular statement. So, basic statements are singular (existential) statements.


Definition of falsifiability

Thornton says that basic statements correspond to particular "observation-reports". He then gives Popper's definition of falsifiability: As in the case of actual falsifiers, decisions must be taken by scientists to accept a logical structure and its associated empirical basis, but these are usually part of a background knowledge that scientists have in common and, often, discussion is not necessary. The first decision described by Lakatos is implicit in this agreement, but the other decisions are not needed. The agreement exists only in principle. This is where the logical/methodological distinction becomes important. When an actual falsifier is proposed, the technology used is considered in detail and an actual agreement is needed. This may require using a deeper empirical basis, to make sure that the properties or values used in the falsifier were obtained correctly. Popper says that despite the fact that the empirical basis can be shaky, the above definition is simply the formalization of a natural requirement on scientific theories, without which the whole logical process of science would not be possible.


Initial condition and prediction in falsifiers of laws

In his analysis of universal laws, Popper conclusion was that laws must "allow us to deduce, roughly speaking, more ''empirical'' singular statements than we can deduce from the initial conditions alone." A singular statement that has only one part cannot contradict a universal law. To contradict an universal law, a falsifier must have two parts: the initial condition and the singular statement that contradicts the prediction as in C \Rightarrow P in which C = "the thing here is a swan" and P = "the thing here is a white swan". However, falsifiers need not have two parts in the definition itself. In this way, the definition is more general and allows basic statements to be falsifiable. For example, "the thing here is a black swan" is falsifiable, because it is contradicted by the falsifier "the thing here is a white swan". Popper wrote that criteria that require that a law must be predictive, just as is required by falsifiability when applied to laws, "have been put forward as criteria of the meaningfulness of sentences (rather than as criteria of demarcation applicable to theoretical systems) again and again after the publication of my book, even by critics who pooh-poohed my criterion of falsifiability."


Necessity to specify the empirical basis

discussed statements such as "All men are mortal." This is not falsifiable, because it does not matter how old a man is, he might die next year. Maxwell said that this statement is nevertheless useful, because it is often corroborated. He coined the term "corroboration without demarcation". Popper's view is that it is indeed useful, because he considers that metaphysical statements can be useful, but also because it is indirectly corroborated by its agreement with the falsifiable law "All men die before the age of 150." For Popper, if no such falsifiable law exists, then the metaphysical law is less useful, because it is not indirectly corroborated. This kind of non-falsifiable statements in science was noticed by Carnap as early as 1937. Maxwell also used the example "All solids have a melting point." This is not falsifiable, because maybe the melting point will be reached at a higher temperature. The law is falsifiable and more useful if we specify an upper bound on melting points or a way to calculate this upper bound. Another example from Maxwell is "All
beta decay In nuclear physics, beta decay (β-decay) is a type of radioactive decay in which an atomic nucleus emits a beta particle (fast energetic electron or positron), transforming into an isobar of that nuclide. For example, beta decay of a neutron ...
s are accompanied with a neutrino emission from the same nucleus." This is also not falsifiable, because maybe the neutrino can be detected in a different manner. The law is falsifiable and much more useful from a scientific point of view, if the method to detect the neutrino is specified. Maxwell said that most scientific laws are metaphysical statements of this kind, which, Popper said, need to be made more precise before they can be indirectly corroborated. In other words, specific technologies must be provided to make the statements inter-subjectively-verifiable, i.e., so that scientists know what the falsification or its failure actually means. In his critique of the falsifiability criterion, Maxwell considered the requirement for decisions in the falsification of both the emission of neutrinos and the existence of the melting point. For example, he pointed out that had no neutrino been detected, it could have been because some conservation law is false. Popper did not argue against the problems of falsification per se. He always acknowledged these problems. His response was at the logical level. For example, he pointed out that, if a specific way is given to trap the neutrino, then, at the level of the language, the statement is falsifiable, because "no neutrino was detected after using this specific way" formally contradicts it (and it is inter-subjectively-verifiable—people can repeat the experiment).


Falsifiability in model theory

Herbert A. Simon Herbert Alexander Simon (June 15, 1916 – February 9, 2001) was an American scholar whose work influenced the fields of computer science, economics, and cognitive psychology. His primary research interest was decision-making within organi ...
studied the semantic aspects of falsifiability. There it is proposed that two formal requirements govern a formally defined and stringent falsifiability that a theory must satisfy to qualify as scientific: that they be finitely and irrevocably testable. These studies were done in the perspective that a logic is a relation between formal sentences in languages and a collection of mathematical structures, each of which is considered a model within model theory. The relation, usually denoted \models \phi, says the formal sentence \phi is true when interpreted in the structure —it provides the semantic of the languages.This perspective can be found in any text on model theory. For example, see . According to Rynasiewicz, in this semantic perspective, Popperian falsifiability means that in some observation structure (in the collection) there exists a set of observations which refutes the theory. A stronger notion of falsifiability was considered, which requires that all structures in the collection that cannot be expanded to a structure that satisfies \phi contain such a contradicting set of observations. This stronger definition makes sense, because it says that we want a falsifier whenever the theory is actually false. It also implies other interesting properties, but it is not the usual falsifiability. For example, « all swans are white and there exists a white raven » is falsifiable in the usual sense, but not strongly falsifiable, because in the case where all swans are white and all ravens are black we cannot find a falsifier. The fact that all ravens are black contradicts the theory, but it is not a singular statement, not a possible observation.


Examples


Newton's theory

Lakatos suggested that Newton's theory was as difficult to show to be falsifiable as
Freud's Freud (aka Freud's) is a café- bar in a Victorian former church building at 119 Walton Street in Jericho, Oxford, England. The Freud café is located opposite Great Clarendon Street and the Oxford University Press is also opposite to the so ...
psychoanalytic theory. To refute this, Popper gave the example of an apple that moves from the ground up to a branch and then starts to dance from branch to branch. According to Popper's definition, this is a basic statement and a potential falsifier for Newton's theory, because the position of the apple at different times can be measured. This appears
controversial Controversy (, ) is a state of prolonged public dispute or debate, usually concerning a matter of conflicting opinion or point of view. The word was coined from the Latin '' controversia'', as a composite of ''controversus'' – "turned in an opp ...
, because Newtonian physics does not deny that forces stronger than Earth's gravity can act on the apple. However, the definition of falsifiability only asserts the well-established fact that Newton's law is predictive, that is, it prohibits certain states of affairs. To this end, it restricts itself to what the law formally says about the basic statements, just as when theoretical physicists compute the directory of a rocket and ignores all methodological considerations that are not a part of the initial conditions that they decided to consider, including these extra forces, because these have been known since at least Duhem to imply the impossibility of predictions.


Einstein's equivalence principle

Another example of a basic statement is "The inert mass of this object is ten times larger than its gravitational mass." This is a basic statement because the inert mass and the gravitational mass can both be measured separately, even though it never happens that they are different. It is, as described by Popper, a valid falsifier for Einstein's equivalence principle.


Evolution


Industrial melanism

In a discussion of the theory of evolution, Popper mentioned industrial melanism as an example of a falsifiable law. A corresponding basic statement that acts as a potential falsifier is "In this industrial area, the relative fitness of the white-bodied
peppered moth The peppered moth (''Biston betularia'') is a temperate species of Nocturnality, night-flying moth. It is mostly found in the northern hemisphere in places like Asia, Europe and North America. Peppered moth evolution is an example of populatio ...
is high." Here "fitness" means "reproductive success over the next generation". It is a basic statement, because it is possible to separately determine the kind of environment, industrial vs natural, and the relative fitness of the white-bodied form (relative to the black-bodied form) in an area, even though it never happens that the white-bodied form has a high relative fitness in an industrial area.


Precambrian rabbit

A famous example of a basic statement from
J. B. S. Haldane John Burdon Sanderson Haldane (; 5 November 18921 December 1964), nicknamed "Jack" or "JBS", was a British-born scientist who later moved to India and acquired Indian citizenship. He worked in the fields of physiology, genetics, evolutionary ...
is " hese arefossil rabbits in the Precambrian era." This is a basic statement because it is possible to find a fossil rabbit and to determine that the date of a fossil is in the Precambrian era, even though it never happens that the date of a rabbit fossil is in the Precambrian era. This shows the scientific character of paleontology, because it contradicts the hypothesis in paleontology that all mammals existed in a much more recent era. Despite opinions to the contrary.
Richard Dawkins Richard Dawkins (born 26 March 1941) is a British evolutionary biology, evolutionary biologist, zoologist, science communicator and author. He is an Oxford fellow, emeritus fellow of New College, Oxford, and was Simonyi Professor for the Publ ...
adds that any other modern animal, such as a hippo, would suffice.


Unfalsifiable statements

A simple example of a non-basic statement is "This angel does not have large wings." It is not a basic statement, because though the absence of large wings can be observed, no technology (independent of the presence of wings) exists to identify angels. Even if it is accepted that angels exist, the sentence "All angels have large wings" is not falsifiable. Another example from Popper of a non-basic statement is "This human action is altruistic." It is not a basic statement, because no accepted technology allows us to determine whether or not an action is motivated by self-interest. Because no basic statement falsifies it, the statement that "All human actions are egotistic, motivated by self-interest" is thus not falsifiable.


Omphalos hypothesis

Some adherents of
young-Earth creationism Young Earth creationism (YEC) is a form of creationism which holds as a central tenet that the Earth and its lifeforms were created by supernatural acts of the Abrahamic God between about 10,000 and 6,000 years ago, contradicting established s ...
make an argument (called the Omphalos hypothesis after the Greek word for navel) that the world was created with the appearance of age; e.g., the sudden appearance of a mature chicken capable of laying eggs. This ad hoc hypothesis introduced into young-Earth creationism is unfalsifiable because it says that the time of creation (of a species) measured by the accepted technology is illusory and no accepted technology is proposed to measure the claimed "actual" time of creation. Moreover, if the ad hoc hypothesis says that the world was created as we observe it today without stating further laws, by definition it cannot be contradicted by observations and thus is not falsifiable. This is discussed by Dienes in the case of a variation on the Omphalos hypothesis, which, in addition, specifies that God made the creation in this way to test our faith.


Natural selection

In the 5th and 6th editions of ''
On the Origin of Species ''On the Origin of Species'' (or, more completely, ''On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life'')The book's full original title was ''On the Origin of Species by M ...
'', following a suggestion of
Alfred Russel Wallace Alfred Russel Wallace (8 January 1823 – 7 November 1913) was an English naturalist, explorer, geographer, anthropologist, biologist and illustrator. He independently conceived the theory of evolution through natural selection; his 1858 pap ...
, Darwin used "Survival of the fittest", an expression first coined by
Herbert Spencer Herbert Spencer (27 April 1820 – 8 December 1903) was an English polymath active as a philosopher, psychologist, biologist, sociologist, and anthropologist. Spencer originated the expression "survival of the fittest", which he coined in '' ...
, as a synonym for
Natural Selection Natural selection is the differential survival and reproduction of individuals due to differences in phenotype. It is a key mechanism of evolution, the change in the Heredity, heritable traits characteristic of a population over generation ...
. Popper and others said that the most widely accepted definition of "fitness" in modern biology, namely
reproductive success Reproductive success is an individual's production of offspring per breeding event or lifetime. This is not limited by the number of offspring produced by one individual, but also the reproductive success of these offspring themselves. Reproduct ...
, the expression "survival of the fittest" is a tautology. Darwinist
Ronald Fisher Sir Ronald Aylmer Fisher (17 February 1890 – 29 July 1962) was a British polymath who was active as a mathematician, statistician, biologist, geneticist, and academic. For his work in statistics, he has been described as "a genius who a ...
worked out mathematical theorems to help answer questions regarding natural selection. But, for Popper and others, no (falsifiable) law of Natural Selection has been offered, because these tools apply only to certain rare traits. Instead, for Popper, the work of Fisher and others on Natural Selection is part of an important and successful metaphysical research program.


Mathematics

Popper said that some unfalsifiable statements may be useful to science. Mathematical statements are good examples. Like all
formal science Formal science is a branch of science studying disciplines concerned with abstract structures described by formal systems, such as logic, mathematics, statistics, theoretical computer science, artificial intelligence, information theory, game t ...
s, mathematics is not concerned with the validity of theories based on observations in the
empirical Empirical evidence is evidence obtained through sense experience or experimental procedure. It is of central importance to the sciences and plays a role in various other fields, like epistemology and law. There is no general agreement on how t ...
world, but rather, mathematics is the study of abstract topics such as
quantity Quantity or amount is a property that can exist as a multitude or magnitude, which illustrate discontinuity and continuity. Quantities can be compared in terms of "more", "less", or "equal", or by assigning a numerical value multiple of a u ...
,
structure A structure is an arrangement and organization of interrelated elements in a material object or system, or the object or system so organized. Material structures include man-made objects such as buildings and machines and natural objects such as ...
,
space Space is a three-dimensional continuum containing positions and directions. In classical physics, physical space is often conceived in three linear dimensions. Modern physicists usually consider it, with time, to be part of a boundless ...
and
change Change, Changed or Changing may refer to the below. Other forms are listed at Alteration * Impermanence, a difference in a state of affairs at different points in time * Menopause, also referred to as "the change", the permanent cessation of t ...
. Mathematical methods are, however, applied in constructing and testing models dealing with observable
reality Reality is the sum or aggregate of everything in existence; everything that is not imagination, imaginary. Different Culture, cultures and Academic discipline, academic disciplines conceptualize it in various ways. Philosophical questions abo ...
.
Albert Einstein Albert Einstein (14 March 187918 April 1955) was a German-born theoretical physicist who is best known for developing the theory of relativity. Einstein also made important contributions to quantum mechanics. His mass–energy equivalence f ...
wrote, "One reason why mathematics enjoys special esteem, above all other sciences, is that its laws are absolutely certain and indisputable, while those of other sciences are to some extent debatable and in constant danger of being overthrown by newly discovered facts."


Historicism

Popper distinguished the original theory of Marx and what came to be known as Marxism. He claimed that the original theory contained genuine scientific laws. Though they could not make preordained predictions, these laws constrained how changes occur in society. One of them was that changes cannot "be achieved by the use of legal or political means". In Popper's view, this was both testable and subsequently falsified. "Yet instead of accepting the refutations", Popper wrote, "the followers of Marx re-interpreted both the theory and the evidence in order to make them agree. ... They thus gave a 'conventionalist twist' to the theory; and by this stratagem, they destroyed its much advertised claim to scientific status." Popper's attacks were not directed toward Marxism, or Marx's theories, which were falsifiable, but toward Marxists who he considered to have ignored the falsifications which had happened. Popper more fundamentally criticized 'historicism' in the sense of any preordained prediction of history, given what he saw as human's right, ability and responsibility to control its destiny.


Courts of law

Falsifiability was used in the '' McLean v. Arkansas'' case (in 1982), the ''
Daubert In United States federal law, the ''Daubert'' standard ( ) is a rule of evidence regarding the admissibility of expert witness testimony. A party may raise a ''Daubert'' motion, a special motion ''in limine'' raised before or during trial, to exc ...
'' case (in 1993) and other cases. A survey of 303 federal judges conducted in 1998 found that " oblems with the nonfalsifiable nature of an expert's underlying theory and difficulties with an unknown or too-large error rate were cited in less than 2% of cases."


''McLean v. Arkansas'' case

In the '' McLean v. Arkansas'' case, Judge William Overton used falsifiability as a criterion to determine that "
creation science Creation science or scientific creationism is a pseudoscientific form of Young Earth creationism which claims to offer scientific arguments for certain literalist and inerrantist interpretations of the Bible. It is often presented without ov ...
" was not scientific and should not be taught in
Arkansas Arkansas ( ) is a landlocked state in the West South Central region of the Southern United States. It borders Missouri to the north, Tennessee and Mississippi to the east, Louisiana to the south, Texas to the southwest, and Oklahoma ...
public schools Public school may refer to: *Public school (government-funded), a no-fee school, publicly funded and operated by the government *Public school (United Kingdom), certain elite fee-charging private schools in England and Wales *Great Public Schools, ...
as such (it can be taught as religion). In his testimony, philosopher
Michael Ruse Michael Escott Ruse (21 June 1940 – 1 November 2024) was a British-born Canadian philosopher of science who specialised in the philosophy of biology and worked on the relationship between science and religion, the creation–evolution contr ...
defined the characteristics which constitute science as: * It is guided by natural law; * It has to be explanatory by reference to natural law; * It is testable against the empirical world; * Its conclusions are tentative, i.e., are not necessarily the final word; and * It is falsifiable. In his conclusion related to this criterion Judge Overton stated:


Daubert standard

In several cases, the
United States Supreme Court The Supreme Court of the United States (SCOTUS) is the highest court in the federal judiciary of the United States. It has ultimate appellate jurisdiction over all U.S. federal court cases, and over state court cases that turn on question ...
described scientific methodology using the five Daubert factors, which include falsifiability. The Daubert result cited Popper and other philosophers of science: David H. Kaye said that references to the Daubert majority opinion confused falsifiability and falsification and that "inquiring into the existence of meaningful attempts at falsification is an appropriate and crucial consideration in admissibility determinations."


Statistical theories and falsifiability

Considering the specific detection procedure that was used in the neutrino experiment, without mentioning its probabilistic aspect, Popper wrote, "it provided a test of the much more significant ''falsifiable'' theory that such emitted neutrinos could be trapped in a certain way". Popper was not concerned with the probabilistic aspect of the experiment. Together with Maxwell, who raised the problems of falsification, he was aware that some convention must be adopted to fix what it means to detect or not detect a neutrino. This is Lakatos' third kind of decision. For Popper and most philosophers, some theory underpins observations. The theory that justifies that we conventionally accept the potential falsifier "no neutrino was detected" is statistical. In statistical language, the potential falsifier that can be not rejected statistically is typically the
null hypothesis The null hypothesis (often denoted ''H''0) is the claim in scientific research that the effect being studied does not exist. The null hypothesis can also be described as the hypothesis in which no relationship exists between two sets of data o ...
, as understood even in popular accounts on falsifiability. Statisticians use various techniques to draw conclusions about hypotheses on the basis of available evidence.
Fisher Fisher is an archaic term for a fisherman, revived as gender-neutral. Fisher, Fishers or The Fisher may also refer to: Places Australia * Division of Fisher, an electoral district in the Australian House of Representatives, in Queensland *Elec ...
, Neyman, and
Pearson Pearson may refer to: Organizations Education * Lester B. Pearson College, Victoria, British Columbia, Canada * Pearson College (UK), London, owned by Pearson PLC *Lester B. Pearson High School (disambiguation) Companies * Pearson plc, a UK-based ...
proposed approaches that require no prior probabilities. In contrast,
Bayesian inference Bayesian inference ( or ) is a method of statistical inference in which Bayes' theorem is used to calculate a probability of a hypothesis, given prior evidence, and update it as more information becomes available. Fundamentally, Bayesian infer ...
emphasizes the importance of prior probabilities. Any approach that provides a way to accept or reject a potential falsifier can be used, including Bayes' theorem and estimates of prior probabilities that are made using critical discussions and reasonable assumptions taken from background knowledge. No general rule considers a hypothesis with small Bayesian revised probability to be falsified, because the individual outcomes described will have small probabilities under available evidence without qualifying as genuine anomalies ( Mayo and Popper). Nevertheless, Mayo added, "they can indirectly falsify hypotheses by adding a methodological falsification rule". In general, Bayesian statistics can play a role in the context of inductive logic, which is said to be inductive because implications are generalized to conditional probabilities. According to Popper and others such as Colin Howson, Hume's argument precludes inductive logic, but only when the logic makes no use "of additional assumptions: in particular, about what is to be assigned positive prior probability". Inductive logic is not precluded, especially not when it is a deductively valid application of Bayes' theorem that is used to evaluate the probability of the hypotheses using the observed data and what is assumed about the priors. Gelman and Shalizi mentioned that Bayes' statisticians do not have to disagree with the non-inductivists. Because statisticians often associate statistical inference with induction, Popper's philosophy is often said to have a hidden form of induction. Mayo wrote "The falsifying hypotheses ... necessitate an evidence-transcending (inductive) statistical inference. This is hugely problematic for Popper". Yet, also according to Mayo, Popper s a non-inductivistacknowledged the useful role of statistical inference in the falsification problems: she mentioned that when Popper wrote her "I regret not studying statistics", her thought was "not as much as I do".


Lakatos' falsificationism

Imre Lakatos Imre Lakatos (, ; ; 9 November 1922 – 2 February 1974) was a Hungarian philosopher of mathematics and science, known for his thesis of the fallibility of mathematics and its "methodology of proofs and refutations" in its pre-axiomatic stage ...
divided the problems of falsification into two categories. The first corresponds to decisions that must be agreed upon by scientists before they can falsify a theory. The other is the use of falsifications and corroborations to explain progress in science. Lakatos described four kind of falsificationisms: * Dogmatic falsificationism – ignores both types of problems. * Methodological falsificationism – addresses the first type of problem by accepting that decisions must be taken by scientists. * Naive methodological falsificationism or naive falsificationism – does not do anything to address the second type of problems. * Sophisticated falsificationism – attempts to address both problems. Lakatos used dogmatic and naive falsificationism to describe how Popper changed over time and viewed sophisticated falsificationism as his refinement, but also said that Popper sometimes presents as a sophisticated falsificationist. Popper responded that Lakatos was misrepresenting his intellectual history.


Dogmatic falsificationism

A dogmatic falsificationist rejects that every observation is theory-impregnated, which means that it goes beyond direct experience. For example, the statement "Here is a glass of water" goes beyond experience, because the concepts of glass and water "denote physical bodies which exhibit a certain law-like behaviour" (Popper). This leads to the critique that it is unclear which theory is falsified: the one under study or the one behind the observation. This is sometimes called the ' Duhem–Quine problem'. An example is Galileo's refutation of the theory that celestial bodies are faultless crystal balls. Many claimed that the optical theory of the telescope was false, not the reigning theory of celestial bodies. Another example is the theory that
neutrinos A neutrino ( ; denoted by the Greek letter ) is an elementary particle that interacts via the weak interaction and gravity. The neutrino is so named because it is electrically neutral and because its rest mass is so small ('' -ino'') that it ...
are emitted in
beta decay In nuclear physics, beta decay (β-decay) is a type of radioactive decay in which an atomic nucleus emits a beta particle (fast energetic electron or positron), transforming into an isobar of that nuclide. For example, beta decay of a neutron ...
s. Had they not been observed in the
Cowan–Reines neutrino experiment The Cowan–Reines neutrino experiment was conducted by physicists Clyde Cowan and Frederick Reines in 1956. The experiment confirmed the existence of neutrinos. Neutrinos, subatomic particles with no electric charge and very small mass, had been ...
, many would have considered that the strength of the beta-inverse reaction used to detect the neutrinos was not sufficiently high. At the time, wrote that the possibility that this strength was sufficiently high was a "pious hope". A dogmatic falsificationist ignores the role of auxiliary hypotheses. The assumptions or auxiliary hypotheses of a particular test are all the hypotheses that must be correct in order for the test to perform as expected. The predicted observation that is contradicted depends on the theory and these auxiliary hypotheses. Therefore, whether it is the theory or an auxiliary hypothesis that is falsified by the observation is undetermined. Lakatos gives the example of the path of a planet. If the path contradicts Newton's law, it is not clear what should be rejected: Newton's law or the hypothesis that no other body influenced the path. A dogmatic falsificationist would ignore that and consider that Newton's law is falsified. Lakatos says that Popper's solution to these criticisms of the dogmatic falsificationist requires relaxing the assumption that an observation can show a theory to be false: Popper's solution, in his own words, is to distinguish between states of affairs as logical falsifications and actual methodological falsifications. Popper never relaxed the notion that logical falsifications show that a theory is falsifiable. He always accepted the existence of methodological problems. He always maintained that actual falsifications are not possible. He wrote that one should nor read Lakatos to understand his intellectual history.


Methodological falsificationism

Methodological falsificationism replaces the usual notion of contradicting observation in a falsification with a new notion of 'contradicting observation' (now in quotes). a convention that requires four kinds of decisions with accompanying goals: * selecting all ''basic statements'' (statements that correspond to logically possible observations), * selecting the ''accepted basic statements'' among those basic statements, * making statistical laws falsifiable and * applying the refutation to the specific theory (instead of an auxiliary hypothesis). The experimental falsifiers and falsifications thus depend on decisions in view of accepted technology and associated theory. A fifth decision is mentioned by Lakatos to allow even more theories to be falsified.


Naive falsificationism

According to Lakatos, naive falsificationism is the claim that methodological falsifications can by themselves explain scientific progress. Very often a theory is still useful and used even after it is found in contradiction with some observations. Also, when scientists deal with two or more competing theories which are both corroborated, considering only falsifications, it is not clear why one theory is chosen above the other, even when one is corroborated more often than the other. In fact, a stronger version of the Quine-Duhem thesis says that it is not always possible to rationally pick one theory over another using falsifications. Considering only falsifications, it is not clear why a corroborating experiment should be seen as progress. Lakatos described Popper as being in part a naive falsificationist and in part a sophisticated falsificationist." In his own words, Popper's critical rationalism used both falsifications and the value of a theory in practice to explain progress. Popper distinguishes between the creative, informal process from which accepted basic statements and accepted theories emerge, and the logical, formal process that compares all theories to all basic statements and defines falsifiability without saying how to methodologically accept basic statements and theories. The main issue addressed by Lakatos is whether the methodological side could be made more formal, in particular, whether the decision to select one among competing theories in the light of falsifications and corroborations could be justified using a formal logic. Such logic would be inductive: it justifies a universal law in view of instances. Lakatos and many others claimed that the decision should be so justified. In contradistinction, for Popper, the creative and informal part is guided by methodological rules, which naturally favour theories that are corroborated and have shown their merit over those that are falsified, but this methodology cannot be made rigorous. Popper's way to analyze progress was through
verisimilitude In philosophy, verisimilitude (or truthlikeness) is the notion that some propositions are closer to being true than other propositions. The problem of verisimilitude is the problem of articulating what it takes for one false theory to be close ...
, a way to define how close a theory is to the truth, which he did not consider significant, except as an attempt to describe a concept already accepted in practice. Later, it was shown that the specific definition proposed by Popper cannot distinguish two false theories, as is the case for all theories in the history of science.


Sophisticated falsificationism

Hume explained induction with a theory of the mind that was in part inspired by Newton's theory of gravitation. Popper rejected Hume's explanation and proposed his own mechanism: science progresses by trial and error within an evolutionary epistemology. Hume believed that his psychological induction process follows laws of nature, but that this does not imply the existence of a method of justification based on logical rules. In fact, he argued that any induction mechanism, including the one his theory described could not be justified logically. Similarly, Popper adopted an evolutionary epistemology that implies that some laws explain progress, but insists that the process of trial and error is not rigorous and that an element of irrationality is unavoidable. Though they be rational, these explanations cannot be turned into methods of justification. This was insufficient for philosophers such as
Russell Russell may refer to: People * Russell (given name) * Russell (surname) * Lady Russell (disambiguation) * Lord Russell (disambiguation) ** Bertrand Russell *Justice Russell (disambiguation) Places *Russell Island (disambiguation) *Mount Russel ...
, who once expressed the view that if Hume's problem cannot be solved, "there is no intellectual difference between sanity and insanity" and discussed what is needed for induction to be possible. He argued that for induction to be possible, a law to make inferences from matters of fact is needed and such law, unlike the principles of deductive logic, must be synthetic. He said "the only alternative to this hypothesis is complete scepticism". Lakatos approved Russell's justificationist view. His proposal of sophisticated falsificationism was natural in that context. Therefore, Lakatos urged Popper to find an inductive principle behind the trial and error learning process and sophisticated falsificationism was his own approach to this challenge. Kuhn, Feyerabend, Musgrave and others mentioned and Lakatos himself acknowledged that this attempt failed, because no normative methodology existed—Lakatos' methodology was anarchy in disguise.


Popperian falsificationism

Popper's philosophy is sometimes said to fail to recognize the Quine-Duhem thesis, which would make it a form of dogmatic falsificationism. For example, Watkins wrote "apparently forgetting that he had once said 'Duhem is right .., Popper set out to devise potential falsifiers just for Newton's fundamental assumptions". But, Popper's philosophy is not always qualified of falsificationism in the pejorative manner associated with dogmatic or naive falsificationism. The problems of falsification are acknowledged by the falsificationists. For example, Chalmers pointed out that falsificationists freely admit that observation relies on theory. Thornton, referring to Popper, says that the predictions inferred from conjectures are not directly compared with the facts simply because all observation statements are theory-laden. For the critical rationalists, the problems of falsification are not an issue, because they do not try to make experimental falsifications logical or to logically justify them, nor to use them to logically explain progress. Instead, they rely on critical discussions around experimental falsifications. Lakatos made a distinction between a "falsification" (with quotation marks) in Popper's philosophy and a falsification (without quotation marks) that can be used in a systematic methodology where rejections are justified. He knew that Popper's philosophy had never been about this kind of justification, but claimed that it should have been. Sometimes, Popper and other falsificationists said that when a theory is falsified it is rejected (dogmatic falsificationism), but they said that in the general context of critical rationalism, in which all decisions are open to critical discussions and can be revised. Popper complained that his discussions of rejection are often taken out of context.


Controversies


Creativity versus induction

As discussed in the section , Lakatos and Popper agreed that universal scientific laws cannot be derived logically, except from broader laws that encompass them. However, unlike Popper, Lakatos believed that induction was the only alternative to deduction. He encouraged Popper to explicitly adopt an inductive approach and sought such an inductive method. However, Lakatos’ method never provided precise inductive rules. In response to critiques from
Thomas Kuhn Thomas Samuel Kuhn (; July 18, 1922 – June 17, 1996) was an American History and philosophy of science, historian and philosopher of science whose 1962 book ''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions'' was influential in both academic and ...
,
Paul Feyerabend Paul Karl Feyerabend (; ; January 13, 1924 – February 11, 1994) was an Austrian philosopher best known for his work in the philosophy of science. He started his academic career as lecturer in the philosophy of science at the University of Bri ...
, and Alan Musgrave, Lakatos admitted that his methodology relied on scientists’ judgment. Feyerabend, in ''Against Method'', argued that Lakatos’ methodology was essentially epistemological anarchism in disguise, a view echoed by Musgrave. Later, Feyerabend noted that Lakatos proposed rules, but these rules did not specify when they must be applied and Feyerabend maintained his position. Popper also proposed a methodology with rules, but these were non-inductive, as they did not independently confirm the validity of scientific laws. Instead, they relied on scientists’ creativity or judgment to determine which theories to study, identify significant problems, and propose testable hypotheses. Citing Einstein, Popper argued that this creative process eliminated the need for an inductive methodology or a logical pathway to discover scientific laws.


Ahistorical versus historiographical

Lakatos’ methodology built significantly on Popper’s by incorporating a historical perspective. Lakatos supported his methodology with examples from the history of science. He defined what he called research programmes, that can be either pursued or abandoned. Research programmes are classified as progressive or degenerative; the latter are eventually abandoned. Lakatos claimed that this classification is largely supported by historical evidence. In contrast, Popper did not design his methodology to rigorously analyze the history of science. However, he occasionally called on historical examples. For instance, he noted that highly successful scientific theories were often disproven. He also introduced, before Lakatos, the notion of metaphysical research programs. He never intended to use them in a rigorous inductive methodology, but in a text that inspired Lakatos he discussed how they change over time. Later, he compared them to Kuhn's paradigms. Lakatos removed the "metaphysical" part and sought rigorous inductive rules. Later, he abandoned this research and adopted rules that require judgment. According to Eli Zahar, Lakatos "admitted that the difference between his position and Popper's was so small as to become purely verbal".


State of affairs as falsifier versus actual falsification

In 1974, Lakatos challenged Popper to demonstrate that his theory of falsifiability was itself falsifiable, asking, "Under what conditions would you abandon your demarcation criterion?" Popper responded, "I shall abandon my theory if Professor Lakatos succeeds in showing that Newton's theory is no more falsifiable by observable states of affairs than Freud's." In Popper’s terminology, a "falsifier" is not an actual observation, but instead a hypothetical situation, a state of affairs, a logical concept that as such is not open to evasive methodological explanations. For example, Newton’s law of gravitation states that a brick falls downward. A hypothetical observation that the brick falls upward is a falsifier (demonstrating falsifiability) even if something else such as strings attached to the brick could explain the observation. In 1982,
David Stove David Charles Stove (15 September 1927 – 2 June 1994) was an Australian philosopher whose writings often challenged prevailing academic orthodoxy. He was known for his critiques of postmodernism, feminism, and multiculturalism. Philosophy Hi ...
criticized Popper, claiming that Lakatos' challenge was successful. Stove contended that any observation appearing to contradict Newtonian physics could be explained by other laws or mechanisms, suggesting no truly "non-Newtonian" behavior was possible. Stove claimed that Popper’s counterexamples, such as missiles following a "non-Newtonian trajectory" or objects not falling due to obvious counteracting forces, were either flawed (e.g.,
begging the question In classical rhetoric and logic, begging the question or assuming the conclusion (Latin: ) is an informal fallacy that occurs when an argument's premises assume the truth of the conclusion. Historically, begging the question refers to a fault i ...
) or consistent with Newtonian physics. Popper reiterated that his falsifiability criterion was a purely logical concept, distinct from the practical ability to disprove a theory. He wrote, "An entire literature rests on the failure to observe this distinction."


Routine versus revolutionary science

Kuhn examined periods of normal science and the transitions (revolutions), that separate them. Popper was interested only in revolutions. He claimed that the purpose of science, mathematics, and metaphysics–all forms of knowledge—is to address and solve problems. Kuhn noted that during periods of normal science, scientists use established theories to routinely solve problems, questioning their validity only when the theory fails. This perspective aligns with Popper's view of problem solving, but places more emphasis on solving routine problems that do not challenge the underlying theory. Kuhn claimed that Popper focused too heavily on formal or logical falsifications and did not adequately explain the social and informal aspects of scientific progress.


Unfalsifiability versus falsity of astrology

Popper often used astrology as an example of a
pseudoscience Pseudoscience consists of statements, beliefs, or practices that claim to be both scientific and factual but are incompatible with the scientific method. Pseudoscience is often characterized by contradictory, exaggerated or unfalsifiable cl ...
. He says that it is not falsifiable because both the theory itself and its predictions are too imprecise. Kuhn remarked that many predictions made by astrologers were quite precise and were often falsified.


Epistemological anarchism vs the scientific method

Feyeraband entirely rejected prescriptive methodology, including Lakatos' argument for ''ad hoc'' hypotheses, arguing that science could not have progressed without making use of every available method. He rejected reliance on a scientific method, along with any special authority for science that might derive from such a method. He said that the only possible universally valid methodological rule was
epistemological anarchism Paul Karl Feyerabend (; ; January 13, 1924 – February 11, 1994) was an Austrian philosopher best known for his work in the philosophy of science. He started his academic career as lecturer in the philosophy of science at the University of Bri ...
(anything goes) was the only candidate. Ultimately, he claimed that science's special status derives from the value of the results rather than its method.


Sokal and Bricmont

In ''
Fashionable Nonsense ''Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse of Science'' (UK: ''Intellectual Impostures''), first published in French in 1997 as , is a book by physicists Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont. As part of the so-called science wars, Sokal an ...
,'' physicists
Alan Sokal Alan David Sokal ( ; born January 24, 1955) is an American professor of mathematics at University College London and professor emeritus of physics at New York University. He works with statistical mechanics and combinatorics. Sokal is a critic o ...
and
Jean Bricmont Jean Bricmont (; born 12 April 1952) is a Belgian theoretical physicist and philosopher of science. Professor at the Catholic University of Louvain (UCLouvain), he works on renormalization group and nonlinear differential equations. Since 200 ...
criticised falsifiability. Sokal and Bricmont discuss falsifiability because they see
postmodernist Postmodernism encompasses a variety of artistic, Culture, cultural, and philosophical movements that claim to mark a break from modernism. They have in common the conviction that it is no longer possible to rely upon previous ways of depicting ...
epistemological relativism Factual relativism (also called epistemic relativism, epistemological relativism, alethic relativism, and cognitive relativism) is the philosophical belief that certain facts are not absolute but depend on the perspective from which they are being ...
as a reaction to Popper's description of falsifiability, and more generally, to his theory of science.


See also

* * * * - claim that a ciphertext decrypts to a particular plaintext can be falsified by possible decryption to another potential plaintext * * * * ** ** * * * * * * * ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** * * * *


Notes


Citations


References

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * excerpt
Science as Falsification
* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *


Further reading

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *


External links

* {{Authority control Analytic philosophy Epistemology of science Epistemological theories Karl Popper Razors (philosophy)