HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Euclid's theorem is a fundamental statement in
number theory Number theory is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and arithmetic functions. Number theorists study prime numbers as well as the properties of mathematical objects constructed from integers (for example ...
that asserts that there are infinitely many
prime A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime because the only ways ...
numbers. It was first proven by
Euclid Euclid (; ; BC) was an ancient Greek mathematician active as a geometer and logician. Considered the "father of geometry", he is chiefly known for the '' Elements'' treatise, which established the foundations of geometry that largely domina ...
in his work '' Elements''. There are several proofs of the theorem.


Euclid's proof

Euclid offered a proof published in his work ''Elements'' (Book IX, Proposition 20), which is paraphrased here. Consider any finite list of prime numbers ''p''1, ''p''2, ..., ''p''''n''. It will be shown that there exists at least one additional prime number not included in this list. Let ''P'' be the product of all the prime numbers in the list: ''P'' = ''p''1''p''2...''p''''n''. Let ''q'' = ''P'' + 1. Then ''q'' is either prime or not: *If ''q'' is prime, then there is at least one more prime that is not in the list, namely, ''q'' itself. *If ''q'' is not prime, then some
prime factor A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime because the only ways ...
''p'' divides ''q''. If this factor ''p'' were in our list, then it would also divide ''P'' (since ''P'' is the product of every number in the list). If ''p'' divides ''P'' and ''q'', then ''p'' must also divide the difference of the two numbers, which is (''P'' + 1) − ''P'' or just 1. Since no prime number divides 1, ''p'' cannot be in the list. This means that at least one more prime number exists that is not in the list. This proves that for every finite list of prime numbers there is a prime number not in the list. In the original work, Euclid denoted the arbitrary finite set of prime numbers as A, B, Γ. Euclid is often erroneously reported to have proved this result by contradiction beginning with the assumption that the
finite set In mathematics, particularly set theory, a finite set is a set that has a finite number of elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example, is a finite set with five elements. Th ...
initially considered contains all prime numbers, though it is actually a proof by cases, a direct proof method. The philosopher Torkel Franzén, in a book on logic, states, "Euclid's proof that there are infinitely many primes is not an indirect proof ..The argument is sometimes formulated as an indirect proof by replacing it with the assumption 'Suppose are all the primes'. However, since this assumption isn't even used in the proof, the reformulation is pointless."


Variations

Several variations on Euclid's proof exist, including the following: The
factorial In mathematics, the factorial of a non-negative denoted is the Product (mathematics), product of all positive integers less than or equal The factorial also equals the product of n with the next smaller factorial: \begin n! &= n \times ...
''n''! of a positive integer ''n'' is divisible by every integer from 2 to ''n'', as it is the product of all of them. Hence, is not divisible by any of the integers from 2 to ''n'', inclusive (it gives a remainder of 1 when divided by each). Hence is either prime or divisible by a prime larger than ''n''. In either case, for every positive integer ''n'', there is at least one prime bigger than ''n''. The conclusion is that the number of primes is infinite.


Euler's proof

Another proof, by the Swiss mathematician
Leonhard Euler Leonhard Euler ( ; ; ; 15 April 170718 September 1783) was a Swiss polymath who was active as a mathematician, physicist, astronomer, logician, geographer, and engineer. He founded the studies of graph theory and topology and made influential ...
, relies on the
fundamental theorem of arithmetic In mathematics, the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, also called the unique factorization theorem and prime factorization theorem, states that every integer greater than 1 is prime or can be represented uniquely as a product of prime numbers, ...
: that every integer has a unique prime factorization. What Euler wrote (not with this modern notation and, unlike modern standards, not restricting the arguments in sums and products to any finite sets of integers) is equivalent to the statement that \prod_ \frac=\sum_\frac, where P_k denotes the set of the first prime numbers, and N_k is the set of the positive integers whose prime factors are all in P_k. To show this, one expands each factor in the product as a
geometric series In mathematics, a geometric series is a series (mathematics), series summing the terms of an infinite geometric sequence, in which the ratio of consecutive terms is constant. For example, 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + 1/16 + ⋯, the series \tfrac12 + \tfrac1 ...
, and distributes the product over the sum (this is a special case of the
Euler product In number theory, an Euler product is an expansion of a Dirichlet series into an infinite product indexed by prime numbers. The original such product was given for the sum of all positive integers raised to a certain power as proven by Leonhard E ...
formula for the Riemann zeta function). \begin \prod_ \frac & =\prod_ \sum_ \frac\\ & = \left(\sum_ \frac\right) \cdot \left(\sum_ \frac\right) \cdot \left(\sum_ \frac\right) \cdot \left(\sum_ \frac\right)\cdots \\ & =\sum_ \frac \\ & =\sum_\frac. \end In the penultimate sum, every product of primes appears exactly once, so the last equality is true by the fundamental theorem of arithmetic. In his first corollary to this result Euler denotes by a symbol similar to \infty the "absolute infinity" and writes that the infinite sum in the statement equals the "value" \log\infty, to which the infinite product is thus also equal (in modern terminology this is equivalent to saying that the partial sum up to x of the harmonic series diverges asymptotically like \log x). Then in his second corollary, Euler notes that the product \prod_ \frac converges to the finite value 2, and there are consequently more primes than squares. This proves Euclid's Theorem. In the same paper (Theorem 19) Euler in fact used the above equality to prove a much stronger theorem that was unknown before him, namely that the series \sum_\frac 1p is divergent, where denotes the set of all prime numbers (Euler writes that the infinite sum equals \log\log\infty, which in modern terminology is equivalent to saying that the partial sum up to x of this series behaves asymptotically like \log\log x).


Erdős's proof

Paul Erdős Paul Erdős ( ; 26March 191320September 1996) was a Hungarian mathematician. He was one of the most prolific mathematicians and producers of mathematical conjectures of the 20th century. pursued and proposed problems in discrete mathematics, g ...
gave a proof that also relies on the fundamental theorem of arithmetic. Every positive integer has a unique factorization into a
square-free {{no footnotes, date=December 2015 In mathematics, a square-free element is an element ''r'' of a unique factorization domain ''R'' that is not divisible by a non-trivial square. This means that every ''s'' such that s^2\mid r is a unit of ''R''. ...
number and a
square number In mathematics, a square number or perfect square is an integer that is the square (algebra), square of an integer; in other words, it is the multiplication, product of some integer with itself. For example, 9 is a square number, since it equals ...
. For example, . Let be a positive integer, and let be the number of primes less than or equal to . Call those primes . Any positive integer which is less than or equal to can then be written in the form a = \left( p_1^ p_2^ \cdots p_k^ \right) s^2, where each is either or . There are ways of forming the square-free part of . And can be at most , so . Thus, at most numbers can be written in this form. In other words, N \leq 2^k \sqrt. Or, rearranging, , the number of primes less than or equal to , is greater than or equal to . Since was arbitrary, can be as large as desired by choosing appropriately.


Furstenberg's proof

In the 1950s, Hillel Furstenberg introduced a proof by contradiction using
point-set topology In mathematics, general topology (or point set topology) is the branch of topology that deals with the basic set-theoretic definitions and constructions used in topology. It is the foundation of most other branches of topology, including differ ...
. Define a topology on the integers \mathbb, called the evenly spaced integer topology, by declaring a subset U \subseteq \mathbb to be an
open set In mathematics, an open set is a generalization of an Interval (mathematics)#Definitions_and_terminology, open interval in the real line. In a metric space (a Set (mathematics), set with a metric (mathematics), distance defined between every two ...
if and only if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
it is either the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
, \emptyset, or it is a union of arithmetic sequences S(a,b) (for a \neq 0), where S(a, b) = \ = a \mathbb + b. Then a contradiction follows from the property that a finite set of integers cannot be open and the property that the basis sets S(a, b) are both open and closed, since \mathbb \setminus \ = \bigcup_ S(p, 0) cannot be closed because its complement is finite, but is closed since it is a finite union of closed sets.


Recent proofs


Proof using the inclusion-exclusion principle

Juan Pablo Pinasco has written the following proof. Let ''p''1, ..., ''p''''N'' be the smallest ''N'' primes. Then by the
inclusion–exclusion principle In combinatorics, the inclusion–exclusion principle is a counting technique which generalizes the familiar method of obtaining the number of elements in the union (set theory), union of two finite sets; symbolically expressed as : , A \cup B, ...
, the number of positive integers less than or equal to ''x'' that are divisible by one of those primes is \begin 1 + \sum_ \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor - \sum_ \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor & + \sum_ \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor - \cdots \\ & \cdots \pm (-1)^ \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor. \qquad (1) \end Dividing by ''x'' and letting ''x'' → ∞ gives \sum_ \frac - \sum_ \frac + \sum_ \frac - \cdots \pm (-1)^ \frac. \qquad (2) This can be written as 1 - \prod_^N \left( 1 - \frac \right). \qquad (3) If no other primes than ''p''1, ..., ''p''''N'' exist, then the expression in (1) is equal to \lfloor x \rfloor and the expression in (2) is equal to 1, but clearly the expression in (3) is not equal to 1. Therefore, there must be more primes than  ''p''1, ..., ''p''''N''.


Proof using Legendre's formula

In 2010, Junho Peter Whang published the following proof by contradiction. Let ''k'' be any positive integer. Then according to
Legendre's formula In mathematics, Legendre's formula gives an expression for the exponent of the largest power of a prime ''p'' that divides the factorial ''n''!. It is named after Adrien-Marie Legendre. It is also sometimes known as de Polignac's formula, a ...
(sometimes attributed to de Polignac) k! = \prod_ p^ where f(p,k) = \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor + \left\lfloor \frac \right\rfloor + \cdots. f(p,k) < \frac + \frac + \cdots = \frac \le k. But if only finitely many primes exist, then \lim_ \frac = 0, (the numerator of the fraction would grow singly exponentially while by
Stirling's approximation In mathematics, Stirling's approximation (or Stirling's formula) is an asymptotic approximation for factorials. It is a good approximation, leading to accurate results even for small values of n. It is named after James Stirling, though a related ...
the denominator grows more quickly than singly exponentially), contradicting the fact that for each ''k'' the numerator is greater than or equal to the denominator.


Proof by construction

Filip Saidak gave the following proof by construction, which does not use
reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical argument'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absur ...
or Euclid's lemma (that if a prime ''p'' divides ''ab'' then it must divide ''a'' or ''b''). Since each natural number greater than 1 has at least one prime factor, and two successive numbers ''n'' and (''n'' + 1) have no factor in common, the product ''n''(''n'' + 1) has more different prime factors than the number ''n'' itself.  So the chain of pronic numbers:
1×2 = 2 ,    2×3 = 6 ,    6×7 = 42 ,    42×43 = 1806 ,    1806×1807 = 3263442 , · · ·
provides a sequence of unlimited growing sets of primes.


Proof using the incompressibility method

Suppose there were only ''k'' primes (''p''1, ..., ''p''''k''). By the
fundamental theorem of arithmetic In mathematics, the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, also called the unique factorization theorem and prime factorization theorem, states that every integer greater than 1 is prime or can be represented uniquely as a product of prime numbers, ...
, any positive integer ''n'' could then be represented as n = ^ ^ \cdots ^, where the non-negative integer exponents ''e''''i'' together with the finite-sized list of primes are enough to reconstruct the number. Since p_i \geq 2 for all ''i'', it follows that e_i \leq \lg n for all ''i'' (where \lg denotes the base-2 logarithm). This yields an encoding for ''n'' of the following size (using
big O notation Big ''O'' notation is a mathematical notation that describes the asymptotic analysis, limiting behavior of a function (mathematics), function when the Argument of a function, argument tends towards a particular value or infinity. Big O is a memb ...
): O(\text + k \lg \lg n) = O(\lg \lg n) bits. This is a much more efficient encoding than representing ''n'' directly in binary, which takes N = O(\lg n) bits. An established result in
lossless data compression Lossless compression is a class of data compression that allows the original data to be perfectly reconstructed from the compressed data with no loss of information. Lossless compression is possible because most real-world data exhibits Redundanc ...
states that one cannot generally compress ''N'' bits of information into fewer than ''N'' bits. The representation above violates this by far when ''n'' is large enough since \lg \lg n = o(\lg n). Therefore, the number of primes must not be finite.


Proof using an even-odd argument

Romeo Meštrović used an even-odd argument to show that if the number of primes is not infinite then 3 is the largest prime, a contradiction. Suppose that p_1=2 < p_2 = 3 < p_3 < \cdots < p_k are all the prime numbers. Consider P=3p_3p_4\cdots p_k and note that by assumption all positive integers relatively prime to it are in the set S=\. In particular, 2 is relatively prime to P and so is P-2. However, this means that P-2 is an odd number in the set S, so P-2=1 , or P = 3. This means that 3 must be the largest prime number which is a contradiction. The above proof continues to work if 2 is replaced by any prime p_j with j \in \, the product P becomes p_1p_2\cdots p_\cdot p_\cdots p_k and even vs. odd argument is replaced with a divisible vs. not divisible by p_j argument. The resulting contradiction is that P-p_j must, simultaneously, equal 1 and be greater than 1, which is impossible.


Stronger results

The theorems in this section simultaneously imply Euclid's theorem and other results.


Dirichlet's theorem on arithmetic progressions

Dirichlet's theorem states that for any two positive
coprime In number theory, two integers and are coprime, relatively prime or mutually prime if the only positive integer that is a divisor of both of them is 1. Consequently, any prime number that divides does not divide , and vice versa. This is equiv ...
integer An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s ''a'' and ''d'', there are infinitely many primes of the form ''a'' + ''nd'', where ''n'' is also a positive integer. In other words, there are infinitely many primes that are
congruent Congruence may refer to: Mathematics * Congruence (geometry), being the same size and shape * Congruence or congruence relation, in abstract algebra, an equivalence relation on an algebraic structure that is compatible with the structure * In modu ...
to ''a''
modulo In computing and mathematics, the modulo operation returns the remainder or signed remainder of a division, after one number is divided by another, the latter being called the '' modulus'' of the operation. Given two positive numbers and , mo ...
''d''.


Prime number theorem

Let be the
prime-counting function In mathematics, the prime-counting function is the function counting the number of prime numbers less than or equal to some real number . It is denoted by (unrelated to the number ). A symmetric variant seen sometimes is , which is equal ...
that gives the number of primes less than or equal to , for any real number . The prime number theorem then states that is a good approximation to , in the sense that the limit of the ''quotient'' of the two functions and as increases without bound is 1: \lim_ \frac=1. Using
asymptotic notation Big ''O'' notation is a mathematical notation that describes the limiting behavior of a function when the argument tends towards a particular value or infinity. Big O is a member of a family of notations invented by German mathematicians Pau ...
this result can be restated as \pi(x)\sim \frac. This yields Euclid's theorem, since \lim_ \frac=\infty.


Bertrand–Chebyshev theorem

In
number theory Number theory is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and arithmetic functions. Number theorists study prime numbers as well as the properties of mathematical objects constructed from integers (for example ...
,
Bertrand's postulate In number theory, Bertrand's postulate is the theorem that for any integer n > 3, there exists at least one prime number p with :n < p < 2n - 2. A less restrictive formulation is: for every n > 1, there is always at least one ...
is a
theorem In mathematics and formal logic, a theorem is a statement (logic), statement that has been Mathematical proof, proven, or can be proven. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to esta ...
stating that for any
integer An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
n > 1, there always exists at least one
prime number A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a Product (mathematics), product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime ...
such that n < p < 2n. Equivalently, writing \pi(x) for the
prime-counting function In mathematics, the prime-counting function is the function counting the number of prime numbers less than or equal to some real number . It is denoted by (unrelated to the number ). A symmetric variant seen sometimes is , which is equal ...
(the number of primes less than or equal to x), the theorem asserts that \pi(x) - \pi(\tfrac) \ge 1 for all x \geq 2. This statement was first conjectured in 1845 by Joseph Bertrand (1822–1900). Bertrand himself verified his statement for all numbers in the interval His conjecture was completely proved by
Chebyshev Pafnuty Lvovich Chebyshev ( rus, Пафну́тий Льво́вич Чебышёв, p=pɐfˈnutʲɪj ˈlʲvovʲɪtɕ tɕɪbɨˈʂof) ( – ) was a list of Russian mathematicians, Russian mathematician and considered to be the founding father o ...
(1821–1894) in 1852. (Proof of the postulate: 371–382). Also see Mémoires de l'Académie Impériale des Sciences de St. Pétersbourg, vol. 7, pp. 15–33, 1854 and so the postulate is also called the Bertrand–Chebyshev theorem or Chebyshev's theorem.


Notes


References


External links

*
Euclid's Elements, Book IX, Prop. 20
(Euclid's proof, on David Joyce's website at Clark University) {{Ancient Greek mathematics Articles containing proofs Theorems about prime numbers Infinity