In
formal linguistics, discourse representation theory (DRT) is a framework for exploring meaning under a
formal semantics approach. One of the main differences between DRT-style approaches and traditional
Montagovian approaches is that DRT includes a level of abstract
mental representation
A mental representation (or cognitive representation), in philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, neuroscience, and cognitive science, is a hypothetical internal cognitive symbol that represents external reality or its abstractions.
Mental re ...
s (discourse representation structures, DRS) within its formalism, which gives it an intrinsic ability to handle meaning across sentence boundaries. DRT was created by
Hans Kamp
Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981.
Biography
Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
in 1981. A very similar theory was developed independently by
Irene Heim in 1982, under the name of ''File Change Semantics'' (FCS).
Discourse representation theories have been used to implement
semantic parsers and
natural language understanding systems.
[Rapaport, William J.]
Syntactic semantics: Foundations of computational natural-language understanding
" Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons. 1994. 225-273.
Discourse representation structures
DRT uses ''discourse representation structure''s (DRS) to represent a hearer's mental representation of a discourse as it unfolds over time. There are two critical components to a DRS:
* A set of ''discourse referents'' representing entities that are under discussion.
* A set of ''DRS conditions'' representing information that has been given about discourse referents.
Consider Sentence (1) below:
:(1) A farmer owns a donkey.
The DRS of (1) can be notated as (2) below:
:(2)
,y: farmer(x), donkey(y), owns(x,y)
What (2) says is that there are two discourse referents, x and y, and three discourse conditions ''farmer'', ''donkey'', and ''owns'', such that the condition ''farmer'' holds of x, ''donkey'' holds of y, and ''owns'' holds of the pair x and y.
Informally, the DRS in (2) is true in a given model of evaluation if and only if there are entities in that model that satisfy the conditions. So, if a model contains two individuals, and one is a farmer, the other is a donkey, and the first owns the second, the DRS in (2) is true in that model.
Uttering subsequent sentences results in the existing DRS being updated.
:(3) He beats it.
Uttering (3) after (1) results in the DRS in (2) being updated as follows, in (4) (assuming a way to disambiguate which pronoun refers to which individual).
:(4)
,y: farmer(x), donkey(y), own(x,y), beat(x,y)
Successive utterances of sentences work in a similar way, although the process is somewhat more complicated for more complex sentences such as sentences containing
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
, and
conditionals
Conditional (if then) may refer to:
*Causal conditional, if X then Y, where X is a cause of Y
*Conditional probability, the probability of an event A given that another event B
*Conditional proof, in logic: a proof that asserts a conditional, a ...
.
''Donkey'' anaphora
In one sense, DRT offers a variation of
first-order predicate calculus—its forms are pairs of first-order formulae and the
free variables that occur in them. In traditional natural language
semantics
Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
, only individual sentences are examined, but the context of a dialogue plays a role in meaning as well. For example,
anaphoric pronouns such as ''he'' and ''she'' rely upon previously introduced individual constants in order to have meaning. DRT uses variables for every individual constant in order to account for this problem. A discourse is represented in a ''discourse representation structure'' (DRS), a box with variables at the top and the sentences in the
formal language
In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "alphabet".
The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbols that concatenate into strings (also c ...
below in the order of the original discourse. Sub-DRS can be used for different types of sentences.
One of the major advantages of DRT is its ability to account for
donkey sentences (
Geach 1962) in a principled fashion:
:(5) Every farmer who owns a donkey beats ''it''.
Sentence (5) can be paraphrased as follows: Every farmer who owns a donkey beats the donkey that he/she owns. Under a Montagovian approach, the indefinite ''a donkey'', which is assumed to be inherently an
existential quantifier, ends up becoming a
universal quantifier
In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any", "for all", "for every", or "given an arbitrary element". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by e ...
, an unwelcome result because the change in quantificational force cannot be accounted for in any principled way.
DRT avoids this problem by assuming that indefinites introduce
discourse referents (DRs), which are stored in the mental representation and are accessible (or not, depending on the conditions) to expressions like pronouns and other
anaphoric elements. Furthermore, they are inherently non-quantificational, and pick up quantificational force depending upon the context.
On the other hand, genuine quantifiers (e.g., 'every professor') bear scope. An 'every-
NP' triggers the introduction of a complex condition of the form K1 → K2, where K1 and K2 are sub-DRSs representing the restriction and the scope of the quantification respectively.
Unlike true quantifiers, indefinite noun phrases just contribute a new DR (together with some descriptive material in terms of conditions on the DR), which is placed in a larger structure. This larger structure can be the top-level DRS or some sub-DRS according to the sentence-internal environment of the analyzed noun phrase—in other words, a level that is accessible to an anaphor that comes later.
See also
*
Combinatory categorial grammar
*
Donkey pronoun
*
Montague grammar
Montague grammar is an approach to natural language semantics, named after American logician Richard Montague. The Montague grammar is based on mathematical logic, especially higher-order predicate logic and lambda calculus, and makes use of th ...
*
Minimal recursion semantics
*
Segmented discourse representation theory
References
* Kadmon, N. 2001. Formal Pragmatics: Semantics, Pragmatics, Presupposition, and Focus. Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers.
*
Lewis, David'Adverbs of Quantification'.In ''Formal Semantics of Natural Language''. Edited by Edward L Keenan. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
Cambridge University Press was the university press of the University of Cambridge. Granted a letters patent by King Henry VIII in 1534, it was the oldest university press in the world. Cambridge University Press merged with Cambridge Assessme ...
, 1975. Pages 3–15.
*
Moltmann, Friederike. 1997. Unbound Anaphoric Pronouns: E-Type, Dynamic and Structured Propositions Approaches'. Synthese 153, 2006. Pages 199-260. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-005-5469-x
External links
Boxer, a broad-coverage implementation of DRTThe Handbook of Philosophical LogicDiscourse Representation Theory
SEP Entry
{{Formal semantics
Semantics
Logic
Systems_of_formal_logic