The term "direction of fit" is used in the philosophy of
intentionality
Intentionality is the mental ability to refer to or represent something. Sometimes regarded as the ''mark of the mental'', it is found in mental states like perceptions, beliefs or desires. For example, the perception of a tree has intentionality ...
to distinguish between types of
representations. It is commonly applied in two related senses: first, to distinguish the
mental states
A mental state, or a mental property, is a state of mind of a person. Mental states comprise a diverse class, including perception, pain/pleasure experience, belief, desire, intention, emotion, and memory. There is controversy concerning the exact ...
of belief and desire; and second, to distinguish between types of linguistic
utterances, such as indicative and imperative sentences.
First,
philosophers of mind distinguish between mind-to-world (i.e., mind-to-fit-world) and world-to-mind (i.e., world-to-fit-mind) directions of fit. In the former, mental states such as beliefs are subject to updates in order to fit evidence provided by the world (the mind changes to fit the world, thus beliefs have a mind-to-world direction of fit). In the latter, mental states such as desires motivate the agent to change the world in order to fit the desired state in the mind (the world changes to fit the mind, thus desires have a world-to-mind direction of fit).
Similarly,
philosophers of language, in particular advocates of
speech act theory
In the philosophy of language and linguistics, a speech act is something expressed by an individual that not only presents information but performs an action as well. For example, the phrase "I would like the mashed potatoes; could you please pas ...
such as
John Searle
John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959 and was Willis S. and Mario ...
, distinguish between word-to-world and world-to-word directions of fit. In the former, utterances such as indicative sentences attempt to describe the world; for a statement, the state of affairs is considered appropriate if the content expressed by the words fit the way the world really is (a word-to-world direction of fit). In the latter, utterances such as imperative sentences attempt to cause a change in the world; for an order, the state of affairs is considered appropriate when the world changes to fit the words (a world-to-word direction of fit).
In both cases, the issue is how representations are considered satisfactory. Beliefs and descriptive statements are considered satisfactory when the states of affairs they represent match the world; i.e. when they are true. Desires and orders are considered satisfactory when world matches the state of affairs they represent; i.e. when they are fulfilled.
Overview
In philosophy of mind, a
belief
A belief is a subjective Attitude (psychology), attitude that something is truth, true or a State of affairs (philosophy), state of affairs is the case. A subjective attitude is a mental state of having some Life stance, stance, take, or opinion ...
has a mind-to-world direction of fit. A belief (that p, say) depicts the world as being in a state of affairs such that p is true. Beliefs, some philosophers have argued, aim at the truth and so aim to fit the world. A belief is satisfied when it fits the world.
A desire, on the other hand, normally expresses a yet to be realized state of affairs and so has a world-to-mind direction of fit. A desire that p, unlike a belief, doesn't depict the world as being in the state that p; rather it expresses a desire that the world be such that p is true. Desire is a state that is satisfied when the world fits it.
A way to account for the difference is that a (rational) person that holds the belief that p when confronted with evidence that not-p, will revise his belief, whereas a person that desires that p can retain his desire that p in the face of evidence that not-p.
To a
philosopher of language a word-to-world fit occurs when, say, a sports journalist correctly names Jones as a goal scorer; while if the journalist mistakenly names Smith as the goal scorer, the printed account does ''not'' display a word-to-world fit, and must be altered such that it matches the real world. Conversely, a world-to-word fit occurs when a fan of Smith's team opines that they deserved to win the match, even though they lost. In this case, the world would have to change to make the sports fan's wish become true.
However, in the case of, say, a judge delivering a
death
Death is the end of life; the irreversible cessation of all biological functions that sustain a living organism. Death eventually and inevitably occurs in all organisms. The remains of a former organism normally begin to decompose sh ...
sentence to a criminal declared
guilty by a
jury
A jury is a sworn body of people (jurors) convened to hear evidence, make Question of fact, findings of fact, and render an impartiality, impartial verdict officially submitted to them by a court, or to set a sentence (law), penalty or Judgmen ...
, the utterances of the judge ''alter'' the world, through the fact of that utterance; and, in this case, the judge is generating a world-to-word-to-world fit (see below). So, if the judge's opinion is upheld, the world ''must'' be altered to match the content of the judge's utterance (i.e., the criminal must be executed).
In medieval philosophy
According to
Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas ( ; ; – 7 March 1274) was an Italian Dominican Order, Dominican friar and Catholic priest, priest, the foremost Scholasticism, Scholastic thinker, as well as one of the most influential philosophers and theologians in the W ...
(''
Summa Theologica
The ''Summa Theologiae'' or ''Summa Theologica'' (), often referred to simply as the ''Summa'', is the best-known work of Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274), a scholastic theologian and Doctor of the Church. It is a compendium of all of the main t ...
'', Part I, Question 21, Article 2), there are two kinds of "
truth
Truth or verity is the Property (philosophy), property of being in accord with fact or reality.Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionarytruth, 2005 In everyday language, it is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise cor ...
" (''veritas''), both understood as
correspondence between mind (''intellectus'') or words (''oratio'') and world ("things", ''res''):
In philosophy of language
Perhaps the first to speak of a "direction of fit" was the philosopher
J. L. Austin. Austin did not use the distinction between different directions of fit to contrast commands or expressions of intention to assertions, or desires to beliefs. He rather distinguishes different ways of asserting that an item is of a certain type.
In a detailed analysis of the distinctions between various scenarios, such as (a) mislabeling a triangle as a square (which Austin regarded as an act of linguistic violence) and (b) inaccurately describing a triangular object as a square (which Austin considered an act of factual violence), Austin introduced a conceptual differentiation. He labeled these distinctions as follows:
* "the onus of match": in the case of one wanting to ''match'' X and Y, the distinction between the matching of X to Y and the matching of Y to X; and
* "the direction of fit": in the case of naming something, the difference between the fitting of a name to an item, and the fitting of an item to a name.
The concept of direction of fit can also apply to
speech acts: e.g., statements, guesses and conjectures have word-to-world direction of fit, while
commands and promises have a world-to-word direction of fit.
John Searle
John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959 and was Willis S. and Mario ...
and Daniel Vanderveken assert that there are only four possible "''directions of fit''" in language:
:1. The word-to-world direction of fit.
:In achieving success of fit the propositional content of the
utterance
In spoken language analysis, an utterance is a continuous piece of speech, by one person, before or after which there is silence on the part of the person. In the case of oral language, spoken languages, it is generally, but not always, bounded ...
fits an independently existing state of affairs in the world. E.g.: "We are married".
:2. The world-to-word direction of fit.
:To achieve success of fit the world must change to match the propositional content of the utterance. E.g.: "Will you marry me?", "I want to marry him", "You'd just better marry her, buddy!", etc.
:3. The double direction of fit.
:To achieve success of fit the world is ''thereby'' altered to fit the propositional content by representing the world as being so altered, unlike sense 2. E.g.: "I declare you man and wife". The 'doubled' direction is therefore always world-to-word-to-world. For obvious reasons, Searle calls sentences of this type 'declarations'.
:4. The null or empty direction of fit.
:There is no direct question of achieving success of fit between the propositional content and the world, because success of fit is presupposed by the utterance. E.g.: "I'm glad I married you" presupposes that the speaker is married to the listener.
Searle used this notion of "''direction of fit''" to create a taxonomy of
illocutionary act
The concept of illocutionary acts was introduced into linguistics by the philosopher J. L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. In his framework, ''locution'' is what was said and meant, ''illocution'' is what was do ...
s.
Although
Elizabeth Anscombe
Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe (; 18 March 1919 – 5 January 2001), usually cited as G. E. M. Anscombe or Elizabeth Anscombe, was a British analytic philosopher. She wrote on the philosophy of mind, philosophy of action, philosophi ...
never employed the term "the direction of fit", Searle has strongly argued that the following passage from her work ''Intention'' was, by far, "the best illustration" of the distinction between the tasks of "
ettingthe words (more strictly their propositional content) to match the world...
nd that of gettingthe world to match the words":
In philosophy of mind
According to Velleman, when used in the domain of the
philosophy of mind
Philosophy of mind is a branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of the mind and its relation to the Body (biology), body and the Reality, external world.
The mind–body problem is a paradigmatic issue in philosophy of mind, although a ...
, the concept direction of fit represents the distinguishing feature between two types of
intentional mental state
A mental state, or a mental property, is a state of mind of a person. Mental states comprise a diverse class, including perception, pain/pleasure experience, belief, desire, intention, emotion, and memory. There is controversy concerning the exact ...
s:
:Facta (singular factum', states that currently exist) are states with a mind-to-world direction of fit.
: Examples include
belief
A belief is a subjective Attitude (psychology), attitude that something is truth, true or a State of affairs (philosophy), state of affairs is the case. A subjective attitude is a mental state of having some Life stance, stance, take, or opinion ...
s,
perception
Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
s,
hypotheses
A hypothesis (: hypotheses) is a proposed explanation for a phenomenon. A scientific method, scientific hypothesis must be based on observations and make a testable and reproducible prediction about reality, in a process beginning with an educ ...
, and
fantasies. In the event of a mismatch between the mental state and the world, the mental state is in some sense false or wrong and should perhaps be changed.
:Facienda (singular faciendum, states that are yet to exist) are states with a world-to-mind direction of fit.
:Examples include
intentions and desires. If there is a mismatch between the mental state and the world, the world is, in some sense, wrong and should perhaps be changed.
In some forms of
mind-body dualism, a matching ''factum'' and ''faciendum'' must be present in a person's
mind
The mind is that which thinks, feels, perceives, imagines, remembers, and wills. It covers the totality of mental phenomena, including both conscious processes, through which an individual is aware of external and internal circumstances ...
in order for him to
act intentionally. If a person has the belief that action (A) will lead to state (S), and has the desire that state (S) obtain, then he will perform action (A). The action is directly
caused by simultaneous presence of the two mental states; no further explanation is needed.
According to Velleman:
::''The term "direction of fit" refers to the two ways in which attitudes can relate
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s to the world.''
::''In
cognitive
Cognition is the "mental action or process of acquiring knowledge and understanding through thought, experience, and the senses". It encompasses all aspects of intellectual functions and processes such as: perception, attention, thought, ...
attitudes
uch as belief a proposition is grasped as patterned after the world; whereas in
conative attitudes
uch as desire the proposition is grasped as a pattern for the world to follow.''
::''The propositional object of desire is regarded not as fact – not, that is, as factum, having been brought about – but rather as faciendum, to be brought about: it's regarded not as true but as to be made true.''
Ruth Millikan has also written influentially about representations, noting that many primitive representations used by animals are characterized by a dual direction of fit; she terms such representations "pushmi-pullyu representations." As an example, she cites the role of bee dances in both informing other bees about the location of resources (indicative, or dance-to-world) and directing their action (imperative, or world-to-dance):
Millikan suggests that many perceptual representations (including those in humans) have such a dual function, both providing an agent information about the state of affairs in the world and suggesting action possibilities to change that state of affairs. She further remarked on the similarity between such representations and the role of
affordances in the ecological perception theory of psychologist
J. J. Gibson.
However, Millikan's openness to Gibson's framework has not been typical of philosophers of mind, and later philosophers such as
Bence Nanay have explored the possibility of action-oriented perception without endorsing affordance theory.
The
predictive coding framework of neural representations developed by neuroscientist
Karl Friston and philosopher
Andy Clark has similarly been observed to be an attempt to construe representations with dual direction of fit, uniting predictions (mind-to-world) and actions (world-to-mind).
[Nicholas Shea, "Perception vs Action: The Computations May Be The Same But The Direction Of Fit Differs," ''Behavioral and Brain Sciences'' 36, 2013, pp. 228-229.]
See also
*
Triangle of reference
References
Bibliography
* Anscombe, G.E.M., ''Intention (Second Edition)'', Basil Blackwell, (Oxford), 1963 (first edition 1957).
* Austin, J.L., ''
How to Do Things With Words
John Langshaw Austin (26 March 1911 – 8 February 1960) was an English philosophy of language, philosopher of language and leading proponent of ordinary language philosophy, best known for developing the theory of speech acts.
Austin pointe ...
: The William James Lectures Delivered at Harvard University in 1955'', Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1962.
* Austin, J.L., "How to Talk: Some Simple Ways", ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'', Vol.53, (1953), pp. 227–246.
* Churchland, Paul, "Conceptual progress and word/world relations: In search of the essence of natural kinds", ''Canadian Journal of Philosophy'' 15(1):1–17 (1985)
* Humberstone, I.L.
"Direction of Fit" ''Mind'', Vol.101, No.401, (January 1992), pp. 59–83.
* Kissine, Mikhail. "Direction of fit". ''Logique et Analyse'' 50.198 (2007): 113-128.
* Millikan, R.G., "Pushmi-pullyu Representations", ''Philosophical Perspectives'' Vol. 9: AI, Connectionism and Philosophical Psychology (1995), pp. 185-200.
* Millikan, R.G., "On Reading Signs: Some Differences Between Us and Others," in ''Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach'', ed. D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, MIT Press, 2004.
* Searle, J.R., "A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts", pp. 1–19 in Searle, J.R., ''Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts'', Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1979. (N.B. This is a reprint of the same paper that was published twice, in 1975 and 1976, under two different titles: (a) Searle, J.R., "A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts", pp. 344–369 in Gunderson, K. (ed.), ''Language, Mind, and Knowledge'', University of Minnesota Press, (Minneapolis), 1975; and (b) Searle, J.R., "A Classification of Illocutionary Acts", ''Language in Society'', Vol.5, (1976), pp. 1–24.)
* Searle, J.R., ''Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts'', Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1985.
* Searle, J.R., ''Rationality in Action'', The MIT Press, (Cambridge, Massachusetts), 2001.
* Searle, J.R. & Vanderveken, D., ''Foundations of Illocutionary Logic'', Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1985.
* Velleman, J.D., "The Guise of the Good", ''Noûs'', Vol.26, No.1, (March 1992), pp. 3–26.
{{div col end
Concepts in the philosophy of language
Concepts in the philosophy of mind