In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, especially in
order theory
Order theory is a branch of mathematics that investigates the intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as "this is less than that" or "this precedes that". This article intr ...
, the cofinality cf(''A'') of a
partially ordered set
In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
''A'' is the least of the
cardinalities of the
cofinal subsets of ''A''. Formally,
:
This definition of cofinality relies on the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
, as it uses the fact that every non-empty set of
cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
s has a least member. The cofinality of a partially ordered set ''A'' can alternatively be defined as the least
ordinal ''x'' such that there is a function from ''x'' to ''A'' with cofinal
image
An image or picture is a visual representation. An image can be Two-dimensional space, two-dimensional, such as a drawing, painting, or photograph, or Three-dimensional space, three-dimensional, such as a carving or sculpture. Images may be di ...
. This second definition makes sense without the axiom of choice. If the axiom of choice is assumed, as will be the case in the rest of this article, then the two definitions are equivalent.
Cofinality can be similarly defined for a
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a preordered set in which every finite subset has an upper bound. In other words, it is a non-empty preordered set A such that for any a and b in A there exists c in A wit ...
and is used to generalize the notion of a
subsequence
In mathematics, a subsequence of a given sequence is a sequence that can be derived from the given sequence by deleting some or no elements without changing the order of the remaining elements. For example, the sequence \langle A,B,D \rangle is a ...
in a
net.
Examples
* The cofinality of a partially ordered set with
greatest element
In mathematics, especially in order theory, the greatest element of a subset S of a partially ordered set (poset) is an element of S that is greater than every other element of S. The term least element is defined duality (order theory), dually ...
is 1 as the set consisting only of the greatest element is cofinal (and must be contained in every other cofinal subset).
** In particular, the cofinality of any nonzero finite ordinal, or indeed any finite directed set, is 1, since such sets have a greatest element.
* Every cofinal subset of a partially ordered set must contain all
maximal elements of that set. Thus the cofinality of a finite partially ordered set is equal to the number of its maximal elements.
** In particular, let
be a set of size
and consider the set of subsets of
containing no more than
elements. This is partially ordered under inclusion and the subsets with
elements are maximal. Thus the cofinality of this poset is
choose
* A subset of the
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s
is cofinal in
if and only if it is infinite, and therefore the cofinality of
is
Thus
is a
regular cardinal.
* The cofinality of the
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s with their usual ordering is
since
is cofinal in
The usual ordering of
is not
order isomorphic to
the
cardinality of the real numbers, which has cofinality strictly greater than
This demonstrates that the cofinality depends on the order; different orders on the same set may have different cofinality.
Properties
If
admits a
totally ordered
In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X:
# a \leq a ( r ...
cofinal subset, then we can find a subset
that is well-ordered and cofinal in
Any subset of
is also well-ordered. Two cofinal subsets of
with minimal cardinality (that is, their cardinality is the cofinality of
) need not be order isomorphic (for example if
then both
and
viewed as subsets of
have the countable cardinality of the cofinality of
but are not order isomorphic). But cofinal subsets of
with minimal order type will be order isomorphic.
Cofinality of ordinals and other well-ordered sets
The cofinality of an ordinal
is the smallest ordinal
that is the
order type
In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
of a
cofinal subset of
The cofinality of a set of ordinals or any other
well-ordered set is the cofinality of the order type of that set.
Thus for a
limit ordinal
In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
there exists a
-indexed strictly increasing sequence with limit
For example, the cofinality of
is
because the sequence
(where
ranges over the natural numbers) tends to
but, more generally, any countable limit ordinal has cofinality
An uncountable limit ordinal may have either cofinality
as does
or an uncountable cofinality.
The cofinality of 0 is 0. The cofinality of any
successor ordinal
In set theory, the successor of an ordinal number ''α'' is the smallest ordinal number greater than ''α''. An ordinal number that is a successor is called a successor ordinal. The ordinals 1, 2, and 3 are the first three successor ordinals ...
is 1. The cofinality of any nonzero limit ordinal is an infinite regular cardinal.
Regular and singular ordinals
A regular ordinal is an ordinal that is equal to its cofinality. A singular ordinal is any ordinal that is not regular.
Every regular ordinal is the
initial ordinal of a cardinal. Any limit of regular ordinals is a limit of initial ordinals and thus is also initial but need not be regular. Assuming the axiom of choice,
is regular for each
In this case, the ordinals
and
are regular, whereas
and
are initial ordinals that are not regular.
The cofinality of any ordinal
is a regular ordinal, that is, the cofinality of the cofinality of
is the same as the cofinality of
So the cofinality operation is
idempotent
Idempotence (, ) is the property of certain operations in mathematics and computer science whereby they can be applied multiple times without changing the result beyond the initial application. The concept of idempotence arises in a number of pl ...
.
Cofinality of cardinals
If
is an infinite cardinal number, then
is the least cardinal such that there is an
unbounded function from
to
is also the cardinality of the smallest set of strictly smaller cardinals whose sum is
more precisely
That the set above is nonempty comes from the fact that
that is, the
disjoint union
In mathematics, the disjoint union (or discriminated union) A \sqcup B of the sets and is the set formed from the elements of and labelled (indexed) with the name of the set from which they come. So, an element belonging to both and appe ...
of
singleton sets. This implies immediately that
The cofinality of any totally ordered set is regular, so
Using
König's theorem, one can prove
and
for any infinite cardinal
The last inequality implies that the cofinality of the cardinality of the continuum must be uncountable. On the other hand,
the ordinal number ω being the first infinite ordinal, so that the cofinality of
is card(ω) =
(In particular,
is singular.) Therefore,
(Compare to the
continuum hypothesis
In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states:
Or equivalently:
In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
, which states
)
Generalizing this argument, one can prove that for a limit ordinal
On the other hand, if the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
holds, then for a successor or zero ordinal
See also
*
*
References
*
Jech, Thomas, 2003. ''Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded''. Springer. .
*
Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. ''Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs''. Elsevier. .
{{Order theory
Cardinal numbers
Order theory
Ordinal numbers
Set theory