HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using recursive ordinal notations.


The Church–Kleene ordinal and variants

The smallest non-recursive ordinal is the Church Kleene ordinal, \omega_1^, named after
Alonzo Church Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
and S. C. Kleene; its
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
is the set of all
recursive ordinal In mathematics, specifically computability and set theory, an ordinal \alpha is said to be computable or recursive if there is a computable well-ordering of a computable subset of the natural numbers having the order type \alpha. It is easy to ch ...
s. Since the successor of a recursive ordinal is recursive, the Church–Kleene ordinal is a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
. It is also the smallest ordinal that is not hyperarithmetical, and the smallest admissible ordinal after \omega (an ordinal \alpha is called admissible if L_\alpha \models \mathsf.) The \omega_1^-recursive subsets of \omega are exactly the \Delta^1_1 subsets of \omega.D. Madore
A Zoo of Ordinals
(2017). Accessed September 2021.
The notation \omega_1^ is in reference to \omega_1, the
first uncountable ordinal In mathematics, the first uncountable ordinal, traditionally denoted by \omega_1 or sometimes by \Omega, is the smallest ordinal number that, considered as a set, is uncountable. It is the supremum (least upper bound) of all countable ordinals. Whe ...
, which is the set of all countable ordinals, analogously to how the Church-Kleene ordinal is the set of all recursive ordinals. Some old sources use \omega_1 to denote the Church-Kleene ordinal.W. Richter, P. Aczel
Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals
(1973, p.15). Accessed 2021 October 28.
For a set x\subseteq\mathbb N, a set is x-computable if it is computable from a Turing machine with an oracle state that queries x. The relativized Church–Kleene ordinal \omega_1^x is the supremum of the order types of x-computable relations. The Friedman-Jensen-Sacks theorem states that for every countable admissible ordinal \alpha, there exists a set x such that \alpha=\omega_1^x. \omega_\omega^, first defined by Stephen G. Simpson is an extension of the Church–Kleene ordinal. This is the smallest limit of admissible ordinals, yet this ordinal is not admissible. Alternatively, this is the smallest α such that L_\alpha \cap \mathsf(\omega) is a model of \Pi^1_1-comprehension.D. Madore
A Zoo of Ordinals
(2017). Accessed September 2021.


Recursively ordinals

The \alphath admissible ordinal is sometimes denoted by \tau_\alpha.J. Barwise, ''Admissible Sets and Structures'' (1976), pp.174--176. Perspectives in Logic, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 3-540-07451-1. Recursively "''x"'' ordinals, where "x" typically represents a
large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least ...
property, are kinds of nonrecursive ordinals. Rathjen has called these ordinals the "recursively large counterparts" of ''x'', however the use of "recursively large" here is not to be confused with the notion of an ordinal being recursive. An ordinal \alpha is called ''recursively inaccessible'' if it is admissible and a limit of admissibles. Alternatively, \alpha is recursively inaccessible iff \alpha is the \alphath admissible ordinal, or iff L_\alpha \models \mathsf, an extension of
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC) and is considerably weak ...
stating that each set is contained in a model of Kripke–Platek set theory. Under the condition that L_\alpha\vDash\textrm ("every set is hereditarily countable"), \alpha is recursively inaccessible iff L_\alpha \cap \mathsf(\omega) is a model of \Delta^1_2-comprehension. An ordinal \alpha is called ''recursively hyperinaccessible'' if it is recursively inaccessible and a limit of recursively inaccessibles, or where \alpha is the \alphath recursively inaccessible. Like "hyper-inaccessible cardinal", different authors conflict on this terminology. An ordinal \alpha is called ''recursively Mahlo'' if it is admissible and for any \alpha-recursive function f : \alpha \rightarrow \alpha there is an admissible \beta < \alpha such that \left\\subseteq\beta (that is, \beta is closed under f). Mirroring the Mahloness hierarchy, \alpha is ''recursively \gamma-Mahlo'' for an ordinal \gamma if it is admissible and for any \alpha-recursive function f : \alpha \rightarrow \alpha there is an admissible ordinal \beta < \alpha such that \beta is closed under f, and \beta is recursively \delta-Mahlo for all \delta<\gamma. An ordinal \alpha is called ''recursively weakly compact'' if it is \Pi_3-reflecting, or equivalently, 2-admissible. These ordinals have strong recursive Mahloness properties, if α is \Pi_3-reflecting then \alpha is recursively \alpha-Mahlo.


Weakenings of stable ordinals

An ordinal \alpha is stable if L_\alpha is a \Sigma_1- elementary-substructure of L, denoted L_\alpha\preceq_1 L. These are some of the largest named nonrecursive ordinals appearing in a model-theoretic context, for instance greater than \min\ for any computably axiomatizable theory T.Proposition 0.7. There are various weakenings of stable ordinals: * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (+1)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_. ** The smallest (+1)-stable ordinal is much larger than the smallest recursively weakly compact ordinal: it has been shown that the smallest (+1)-stable ordinal is \Pi_n-reflecting for all finite n. ** In general, a countable ordinal \alpha is called (+\beta)-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^+)-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_, where \beta^+ is the smallest admissible ordinal > \beta. The smallest (^+)-stable ordinal is again much larger than the smallest (+1)-stable or the smallest (+\beta)-stable for any constant \beta. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^)-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_, where \beta^ are the two smallest admissible ordinals > \beta. The smallest (^)-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest \Sigma^1_1-reflecting. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called inaccessibly-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_, where \beta is the smallest recursively inaccessible ordinal > \alpha. The smallest inaccessibly-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest (^)-stable. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called Mahlo-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_, where \beta is the smallest recursively Mahlo ordinal > \alpha. The smallest Mahlo-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest inaccessibly-stable. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called doubly (+1)-stable iff L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_ \preceq_1 L_. The smallest doubly (+1)-stable ordinal is larger than the smallest Mahlo-stable.


Larger nonrecursive ordinals

Even larger nonrecursive ordinals include: * The least ordinal \alpha such that L_\alpha \preceq_1 L_\beta where \beta is the smallest nonprojectible ordinal. * An ordinal \alpha is nonprojectible if \alpha is a limit of ''\alpha''-stable ordinals, or; if the set X = \left\ is unbounded in ''\alpha''. * The ordinal of ramified analysis, often written as \beta_0. This is the smallest \beta such that L_\beta \cap \mathsf(\omega) is a model of second-order comprehension, or L_\beta \models \mathsf, which is \mathsf without the
axiom of power set In mathematics, the axiom of power set is one of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms of axiomatic set theory. It guarantees for every set x the existence of a set \mathcal(x), the power set of x, consisting precisely of the subsets of x. By the axio ...
. * The least ordinal \alpha such that L_\alpha \models \mathsf + \text\omega_1\text. This ordinal has been characterized by Toshiyasu Arai.T. Arai
A Sneak Preview of Proof Theory of Ordinals
(1997, p.17). Accessed 2021 October 28.
* The least ordinal \alpha such that L_\alpha \models \mathsf + \text\omega_1\text. * The least stable ordinal.


References

* * * * * * {{countable ordinals Proof theory Ordinal numbers