Cardinal Characteristics Of The Continuum
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the
mathematical Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
discipline of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, a cardinal characteristic of the continuum is an infinite
cardinal number In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
that may consistently lie strictly between \aleph_0 (the
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
of the set of
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s), and the
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
, that is, the cardinality of the set \mathbb R of all
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s. The latter cardinal is denoted 2^ or \mathfrak c. A variety of such cardinal characteristics arise naturally, and much work has been done in determining what relations between them are provable, and constructing models of set theory for various
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
configurations of them.


Background

Cantor's diagonal argument Cantor's diagonal argument (among various similar namesthe diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof) is a mathematical proof that there are infin ...
shows that \mathfrak c is strictly greater than \aleph_0, but it does not specify whether it is the ''least'' cardinal greater than \aleph_0 (that is, \aleph_1). Indeed the assumption that \mathfrak c = \aleph_1 is the well-known
Continuum Hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
, which was shown to be consistent with the standard ZFC axioms for set theory by
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
and to be independent of it by
Paul Cohen Paul Joseph Cohen (April 2, 1934 – March 23, 2007) was an American mathematician, best known for his proofs that the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice are independent from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, for which he was awarded a F ...
. If the Continuum Hypothesis fails and so \mathfrak c is at least \aleph_2, natural questions arise about the cardinals strictly between \aleph_0 and \mathfrak c, for example regarding Lebesgue measurability. By considering the least cardinal with some property, one may get a definition for an uncountable cardinal that is consistently less than \mathfrak c. Generally one only considers definitions for cardinals that are provably greater than \aleph_0 and at most \mathfrak c as cardinal characteristics of the continuum, so if the Continuum Hypothesis holds they are all equal to \aleph_1.


Examples

As is standard in set theory, we denote by \omega the least infinite ordinal, which has cardinality \aleph_0; it may be identified with the set of natural numbers. A number of cardinal characteristics naturally arise as cardinal invariants for ideals which are closely connected with the structure of the reals, such as the ideal of Lebesgue null sets and the ideal of
meagre set In the mathematical Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itse ...
s.


non(''N'')

The cardinal characteristic \text(\mathcal) is the least cardinality of a
non-measurable set In mathematics, a non-measurable set is a set which cannot be assigned a meaningful "volume". The existence of such sets is construed to provide information about the notions of length, area and volume in formal set theory. In Zermelo–Fraenke ...
; equivalently, it is the least cardinality of a set that is not a
Lebesgue null set In mathematical analysis, a null set is a Lebesgue measurable set of real numbers that has measure zero. This can be characterized as a set that can be covered by a countable union of intervals of arbitrarily small total length. The notio ...
.


Bounding number and dominating number

We denote by \omega^\omega the set of functions from \omega to \omega. For any two functions f:\omega\to\omega and g:\omega\to\omega we denote by f \leq^* g the statement that for all but finitely many n\in\omega, f(n) \leq g(n). The '' bounding number'' \mathfrak b is the least cardinality of an unbounded set in this relation, that is, \mathfrak b = \min(\). The '' dominating number'' \mathfrak d is the least cardinality of a set of functions from \omega to \omega such that every such function is dominated by (that is, \leq^*) a member of that set, that is, \mathfrak d = \min(\). Clearly any such dominating set F is unbounded, so \mathfrak b is at most \mathfrak d, and a diagonalisation argument shows that \mathfrak b>\aleph_0. Of course if \mathfrak c=\aleph_1 this implies that \mathfrak b=\mathfrak d=\aleph_1, but Hechler has shown that it is also consistent to have \mathfrak b strictly less than \mathfrak d .


Splitting number and reaping number

We denote by
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega the set of all infinite subsets of \omega. For any a,b\in
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega, we say that a ''splits'' b if both b \cap a and b \setminus a are infinite. The ''splitting number'' \mathfrak s is the least cardinality of a subset S of
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega such that for all b\in
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega, there is some a\in S such that a splits b. That is, \mathfrak s = \min(\). The ''reaping number'' \mathfrak r is the least cardinality of a subset R of
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega such that no element a of
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
\omega splits every element of R. That is, \mathfrak r = \min(\).


Ultrafilter number

The ultrafilter number \mathfrak u is defined to be the least cardinality of a
filter base In mathematics, a filter on a set X is a family \mathcal of subsets such that: # X \in \mathcal and \emptyset \notin \mathcal # if A\in \mathcal and B \in \mathcal, then A\cap B\in \mathcal # If A\subset B\subset X and A\in \mathcal, then B\in ...
of a non-principal
ultrafilter In the Mathematics, mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a Maximal element, maximal Filter (mathematics), filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P th ...
on \omega. Kunen gave a model of set theory in which \mathfrak u = \aleph_1 but \mathfrak c = \aleph_, and using a countable support iteration of Sacks forcings, Baumgartner and Laver constructed a model in which \mathfrak u = \aleph_1 and \mathfrak c = \aleph_2.


Almost disjointness number

Two subsets A and B of \omega are said to be '' almost disjoint'' if , A\cap B, is finite, and a
family Family (from ) is a Social group, group of people related either by consanguinity (by recognized birth) or Affinity (law), affinity (by marriage or other relationship). It forms the basis for social order. Ideally, families offer predictabili ...
of subsets of \omega is said to be almost disjoint if its members are pairwise almost disjoint. A ''maximal almost disjoint'' ("''mad''") family of subsets of \omega is thus an almost disjoint family \mathcal such that for every subset X of \omega not in \mathcal, there is a set A\in\mathcal such that A and X are not almost disjoint (that is, their
intersection In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their ...
is infinite). The almost disjointness number \mathfrak is the least cardinality of an infinite maximal almost disjoint family. A basic result is that \mathfrak\leq\mathfrak; Shelah
Saharon Shelah Saharon Shelah (; , ; born July 3, 1945) is an Israeli mathematician. He is a professor of mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University in New Jersey. Biography Shelah was born in Jerusalem on July 3, 1945. He is th ...
. On cardinal invariants of the continuum. In J. Baumgartner, D. Martin and S. Shelah (eds) ''Axiomatic Set Theory'', Contemporary Mathematics 31, American Mathematical Society, 1984, pp 183-207.
showed that it is consistent to have the strict inequality \mathfrak<\mathfrak.


Cichoń's diagram

A well-known diagram of cardinal characteristics is Cichoń's diagram, showing all pairwise relations provable in ZFC between 10 cardinal characteristics.


References


Further reading

* Tomek Bartoszyński and Haim Judah. ''Set Theory On the Structure of the Real Line''. A K Peters, 1995. * * * * * {{cite book , last=Halbeisen , first=Lorenz J. , title=Combinatorial Set Theory: With a Gentle Introduction to Forcing , publisher =
Springer-Verlag Springer Science+Business Media, commonly known as Springer, is a German multinational publishing company of books, e-books and peer-reviewed journals in science, humanities, technical and medical (STM) publishing. Originally founded in 1842 in ...
, location=London , year=2012 , others=Springer Monographs in Mathematics , series=Springer Monographs in Mathematics , isbn = 978-1-4471-2172-5 , doi = 10.1007/978-1-4471-2173-2 Cardinal numbers