In
probability theory
Probability theory is the branch of mathematics concerned with probability. Although there are several different probability interpretations, probability theory treats the concept in a rigorous mathematical manner by expressing it through a set o ...
, Boole's inequality, also known as the union bound, says that for any
finite
Finite is the opposite of infinite. It may refer to:
* Finite number (disambiguation)
* Finite set, a set whose cardinality (number of elements) is some natural number
* Finite verb
Traditionally, a finite verb (from la, fīnītus, past partici ...
or
countable
In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural number ...
set of
events, the probability that at least one of the events happens is no greater than the sum of the probabilities of the individual events. This inequality provides an upper bound on the probability of occurrence of at least one of a countable number of events in terms of the individual probabilities of the events. Boole's inequality is named for its discoverer
George Boole
George Boole (; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher, and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in ...
.
Formally, for a countable set of events ''A''
1, ''A''
2, ''A''
3, ..., we have
:
In
measure-theoretic terms, Boole's inequality follows from the fact that a measure (and certainly any
probability measure
In mathematics, a probability measure is a real-valued function defined on a set of events in a probability space that satisfies measure properties such as ''countable additivity''. The difference between a probability measure and the more g ...
) is ''σ''-
sub-additive.
Proof
Proof using induction
Boole's inequality may be proved for finite collections of
events using the method of induction.
For the
case, it follows that
:
For the case
, we have
:
Since
and because the union operation is
associative
In mathematics, the associative property is a property of some binary operations, which means that rearranging the parentheses in an expression will not change the result. In propositional logic, associativity is a valid rule of replacement ...
, we have
:
Since
:
by the
first axiom of probability, we have
:
and therefore
:
Proof without using induction
For any events in
in our
probability space
In probability theory, a probability space or a probability triple (\Omega, \mathcal, P) is a mathematical construct that provides a formal model of a random process or "experiment". For example, one can define a probability space which models t ...
we have
:
One of the axioms of a probability space is that if
are ''disjoint'' subsets of the probability space then
:
this is called ''countable additivity.''
If
then
Indeed, from the axioms of a probability distribution,
:
Note that both terms on the right are nonnegative.
Now we have to modify the sets
, so they become disjoint.
:
So if
, then we know
:
Therefore, we can deduce the following equation
:
Bonferroni inequalities
Boole's inequality may be generalized to find
upper
Upper may refer to:
* Shoe upper or ''vamp'', the part of a shoe on the top of the foot
* Stimulant, drugs which induce temporary improvements in either mental or physical function or both
* ''Upper'', the original film title for the 2013 found fo ...
and
lower bounds on the probability of
finite unions of events.
These bounds are known as Bonferroni inequalities, after
Carlo Emilio Bonferroni; see .
Define
:
and
:
as well as
:
for all integers ''k'' in .
Then, for
odd ''k'' in ,
:
and for
even ''k'' in ,
:
Boole's inequality is the initial case, ''k'' = 1. When ''k'' = ''n'', then equality holds and the resulting identity is the
inclusion–exclusion principle.
Example
Suppose that you are estimating 5 parameters based on a random sample, and you can control each parameter separately. If you want your estimations of all five parameters to be good with a chance 95%, how should you do to each parameter?
Obviously, controlling each parameter good with a chance 95% is not enough because "all are good" is a subset of each event "Estimate ''i'' is good". We can use Boole's Inequality to solve this problem. By finding the complement of event "all fives are good", we can change this question into another condition:
''P( at least one estimation is bad) = 0.05 ≤ P( A
1 is bad) + P( A
2 is bad) + P( A
3 is bad) + P( A
4 is bad) + P( A
5 is bad)''
One way is to make each of them equal to 0.05/5 = 0.01, that is 1%. In another word, you have to guarantee each estimate good to 99%( for example, by constructing a 99% confidence interval) to make sure the total estimation to be good with a chance 95%. This is called Bonferroni Method of simultaneous inference.
See also
*
Diluted inclusion–exclusion principle
*
Schuette–Nesbitt formula
*
Boole–Fréchet inequalities
*
Probability of the union of pairwise independent events
References
Other related articles
*
*
*
*
*
{{PlanetMath attribution, id=6049, title=Bonferroni inequalities
Probabilistic inequalities
Statistical inequalities