Axiom Of Infinity
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In axiomatic set theory and the branches of
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
and
philosophy Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s. It was first published by Ernst Zermelo as part of his
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
in 1908.


Formal statement

Using first-order logic primitive symbols, the axiom can be expressed as follows: \exist \mathrm \ (\exist o \ (o \in \mathrm \ \land \lnot \exist n \ (n \in o)) \ \land \ \forall x \ (x \in \mathrm \Rightarrow \exist y \ (y \in \mathrm \ \land \ \forall a \ (a \in y \Leftrightarrow (a \in x \ \lor \ a = x))))). If the notations of both set-builder and
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
are allowed: \exists \mathrm \, ( \varnothing \in \mathrm \, \land \, \forall x \, (x \in \mathrm \Rightarrow \, ( x \cup \ ) \in \mathrm ) ). Some mathematicians may call a set built this way an inductive set. Hint: In English, it reads: " There exists a set 𝐈 such that the empty set is an element of it, and for every element x of 𝐈, there exists an element y of 𝐈 such that an element of y is either x itself, or, an element of x."


Interpretation and consequences

This axiom is closely related to the von Neumann construction of the natural numbers in set theory, in which the '' successor'' of ''x'' is defined as ''x'' ∪ . If ''x'' is a set, then it follows from the other axioms of set theory that this successor is also a uniquely defined set. Successors are used to define the usual set-theoretic encoding of the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s. In this encoding, zero is the empty set: : 0 = . The number 1 is the successor of 0: : 1 = 0 ∪ = ∪ = = . Likewise, 2 is the successor of 1: : 2 = 1 ∪ = ∪ = = , and so on: : 3 = = ; : 4 = = . A consequence of this definition is that every natural number is equal to the set of all preceding natural numbers. The count of elements in each set, at the top level, is the same as the represented natural number, and the nesting depth of the most deeply nested empty set , including its nesting in the set that represents the number of which it is a part, is also equal to the natural number that the set represents. This construction forms the natural numbers. However, the other axioms are insufficient to prove the existence of the set of ''all'' natural numbers, \mathbb_0. Therefore, its existence is taken as an axiom – the axiom of infinity. This axiom asserts that there is a set I that contains 0 and is closed under the operation of taking the successor; that is, for each element of I, the successor of that element is also in I. Thus the essence of the axiom is: :There is a set, I, that includes all the natural numbers. The axiom of infinity is also one of the von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel axioms.


Extracting the natural numbers from the infinite set

The infinite set I is a superset of the natural numbers. To show that the natural numbers themselves constitute a set, the axiom schema of specification can be applied to remove unwanted elements, leaving the set N of all natural numbers. This set is unique by the
axiom of extensionality The axiom of extensionality, also called the axiom of extent, is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. The axiom defines what a Set (mathematics), set is. Informally, the axiom means that the ...
. To extract the natural numbers, we need a definition of which sets are natural numbers. The natural numbers can be defined in a way that does not assume any axioms except the
axiom of extensionality The axiom of extensionality, also called the axiom of extent, is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. The axiom defines what a Set (mathematics), set is. Informally, the axiom means that the ...
and the axiom of induction—a natural number is either zero or a successor and each of its elements is either zero or a successor of another of its elements. In formal language, the definition says: : \forall n (n \in \mathbf \iff ( = \empty \,\,\lor\,\, \exists k ( n = k \cup \ )\,\,\land\,\, \forall m \in n = \empty \,\,\lor\,\, \exists k \in n ( m = k \cup \ )). Or, even more formally: : \forall n (n \in \mathbf \iff ( forall k (\lnot k \in n) \lor \exists k \forall j (j \in n \iff (j \in k \lor j = k))\; \land :: \forall m (m \in n \Rightarrow forall k (\lnot k \in m) \lor \exists k (k \in n \land \forall j (j \in m \iff (j \in k \lor j = k))))).


Alternative method

An alternative method is the following. Let \Phi(x) be the formula that says "x is inductive"; i.e. \Phi(x) = (\emptyset \in x \wedge \forall y(y \in x \to (y \cup \ \in x))). Informally, what we will do is take the intersection of all inductive sets. More formally, we wish to prove the existence of a unique set W such that : \forall x(x \in W \leftrightarrow \forall I(\Phi(I) \to x \in I)). (*) For existence, we will use the Axiom of Infinity combined with the Axiom schema of specification. Let I be an inductive set guaranteed by the Axiom of Infinity. Then we use the axiom schema of specification to define our set W = \ – i.e. W is the set of all elements of I, which also happen to be elements of every other inductive set. This clearly satisfies the hypothesis of (*), since if x \in W, then x is in every inductive set, and if x is in every inductive set, it is in particular in I, so it must also be in W. For uniqueness, first note that any set that satisfies (*) is itself inductive, since 0 is in all inductive sets, and if an element x is in all inductive sets, then by the inductive property so is its successor. Thus if there were another set W' that satisfied (*) we would have that W' \subseteq W since W is inductive, and W \subseteq W' since W' is inductive. Thus W = W'. Let \omega denote this unique element. This definition is convenient because the principle of induction immediately follows: If I \subseteq \omega is inductive, then also \omega \subseteq I, so that I = \omega. Both these methods produce systems that satisfy the axioms of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
, since the axiom of power set allows us to quantify over the power set of \omega, as in second-order logic. Thus they both completely determine isomorphic systems, and since they are isomorphic under the
identity map Graph of the identity function on the real numbers In mathematics, an identity function, also called an identity relation, identity map or identity transformation, is a function that always returns the value that was used as its argument, unc ...
, they must in fact be equal.


An apparently weaker version

Some old texts use an apparently weaker version of the axiom of infinity, to wit: : \exists x \, ( \exists y \, ( y \in x ) \, \land \, \forall y ( y \in x \, \rightarrow \, \exists z ( z \in x \, \land \, y \subsetneq z ) ) ) \,. This says that ''x'' is non-empty and for every element ''y'' of ''x'' there is another element ''z'' of ''x'' such that ''y'' is a subset of ''z'' and ''y'' is not equal to ''z''. This implies that ''x'' is an infinite set without saying much about its structure. However, with the help of the other axioms of ZF, we can show that this implies the existence of ω. First, if we take the powerset of any infinite set ''x'', then that powerset will contain elements that are subsets of ''x'' of every finite
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
(among other subsets of ''x''). Proving the existence of those finite subsets may require either the axiom of separation or the axioms of pairing and union. Then we can apply the axiom of replacement to replace each element of that powerset of ''x'' by the
initial In a written or published work, an initial is a letter at the beginning of a word, a chapter (books), chapter, or a paragraph that is larger than the rest of the text. The word is ultimately derived from the Latin ''initiālis'', which means '' ...
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
of the same cardinality (or zero, if there is no such ordinal). The result will be an infinite set of ordinals. Then we can apply the axiom of union to that to get an ordinal greater than or equal to ω.


Independence

The axiom of infinity cannot be proved from the other axioms of ZFC if they are consistent. (To see why, note that ZFC implies the consistency of ZFC − Infinity and use Gödel's Second incompleteness theorem.) The negation of the axiom of infinity cannot be derived from the rest of the axioms of ZFC, if they are consistent. (This is tantamount to saying that ZFC is consistent, if the other axioms are consistent.) Thus, ZFC implies neither the axiom of infinity nor its negation and is compatible with either. Indeed, using the von Neumann universe, we can build a model of ZFC − Infinity + (¬Infinity). It is V_\omega \!, the class of hereditarily finite sets, with the inherited membership relation. Note that if the axiom of the empty set is not taken as a part of this system (since it can be derived from ZF + Infinity), then the empty domain also satisfies ZFC − Infinity + ¬Infinity, as all of its axioms are universally quantified, and thus trivially satisfied if no set exists. The cardinality of the set of natural numbers, aleph null (\aleph_0), has many of the properties of a large cardinal. Thus the axiom of infinity is sometimes regarded as the first ''large cardinal axiom'', and conversely large cardinal axioms are sometimes called stronger axioms of infinity.


See also

* Peano axioms * Finitism


References

*
Paul Halmos Paul Richard Halmos (; 3 March 1916 – 2 October 2006) was a Kingdom of Hungary, Hungarian-born United States, American mathematician and probabilist who made fundamental advances in the areas of mathematical logic, probability theory, operat ...
(1960) ''Naive Set Theory''. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company. Reprinted 1974 by Springer-Verlag. . * Thomas Jech (2003) ''Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded''. Springer-Verlag. . * Kenneth Kunen (1980) ''Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs''. Elsevier. . * {{Set theory Axioms of set theory Infinity