
In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, particularly in
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, the aleph numbers are a
sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
of numbers used to represent the
cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
(or size) of
infinite set
In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable.
Properties
The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
s. They were introduced by the mathematician
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ; – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter
aleph
Aleph (or alef or alif, transliterated ʾ) is the first Letter (alphabet), letter of the Semitic abjads, including Phoenician alphabet, Phoenician ''ʾālep'' 𐤀, Hebrew alphabet, Hebrew ''ʾālef'' , Aramaic alphabet, Aramaic ''ʾālap'' � ...
(ℵ).
The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, denoted by
(read ''aleph-nought'', ''aleph-zero'', or ''aleph-null''); the next larger cardinality of a
well-ordered set is
then
then
and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define an infinite
cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
for every
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
as described below.
The concept and notation are due to
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ; – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
,
who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that
infinite sets can have different cardinalities.
The aleph numbers differ from the
infinity
Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is denoted by \infty, called the infinity symbol.
From the time of the Ancient Greek mathematics, ancient Greeks, the Infinity (philosophy), philosophic ...
(
) commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme
limit of the
real number line (applied to a
function or
sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
that "
diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the
extended real number line.
Aleph-zero
(aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an
infinite cardinal. The set of all finite
ordinals, called
or
(where
is the lowercase Greek letter
omega
Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
), also has cardinality
. A set has cardinality
if and only if it is
countably infinite
In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
, that is, there is a
bijection
In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
(one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are
* the set of
natural numbers
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
, irrespective of including or excluding zero,
* the set of all
integer
An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s,
* any infinite subset of the integers, such as the set of all
square numbers or the set of all
prime numbers,
* the set of all
rational number
In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example,
The set of all ...
s,
* the set of all
constructible numbers (in the geometric sense),
* the set of all
algebraic numbers,
* the set of all
computable numbers,
* the set of all
computable functions,
* the set of all binary
strings of finite length, and
* the set of all finite
subset
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
s of any given countably infinite set.
Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals, including for example
,
,
,
,
, and
. For example, the sequence (with
order type ) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers
is an ordering of the set (with cardinality
) of positive integers.
If the
axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
) holds, then
is smaller than any other infinite cardinal, and is therefore the (unique) least infinite ordinal.
Aleph-one
is the cardinality of the set of all countable
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s. This set is denoted by
(or sometimes Ω). The set
is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an
uncountable set
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger t ...
. Therefore,
is the smallest cardinality that is larger than
the smallest infinite cardinality.
The definition of
implies (in ZF,
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
''without'' the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between
and
If the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is
totally ordered
In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X:
# a \leq a ( r ...
, and thus
is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. One can show one of the most useful properties of the set : Any countable subset of
has an upper bound in
(this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable). This fact is analogous to the situation in
: Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and
finite unions of finite sets are finite.
An example application of the ordinal
is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the
σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g.
Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (
vector space
In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set (mathematics), set whose elements, often called vector (mathematics and physics), ''vectors'', can be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called sc ...
s,
groups, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, etc. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via
transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible ''countable'' unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of
Continuum hypothesis
The
cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
of the set of
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s (
cardinality of the continuum
In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
) is 2
. It cannot be determined from
ZFC (
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
augmented with the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis (CH) is equivalent to the identity
:2
=
.
[
]
The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the natural numbers and the real numbers. CH is independent of
ZFC: It can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that
ZFC is
consistent
In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
). That CH is consistent with
ZFC was demonstrated by
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
in 1940, when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of
ZFC. That it is independent of
ZFC was demonstrated by
Paul Cohen in 1963, when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of
ZFC – by the (then-novel) method of
forcing.
[
]
Aleph-omega
Aleph-omega is where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted as . That is, the cardinal number is the least upper bound of .
Notably, is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ''not'' to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s : For any natural number , we can consistently assume that , and moreover it is possible to assume that is as least as large as any cardinal number we like. The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with cofinality . An uncountably infinite cardinal having cofinality means that there is a (countable-length) sequence of cardinals whose limit (i.e. its least upper bound) is (see Easton's theorem). As per the definition above, is the limit of a countable-length sequence of smaller cardinals.
Aleph-''α'' for general ''α''
To define for arbitrary ordinal number , we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number the next larger well-order
In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then calle ...
ed cardinal (if the axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
holds, this is the (unique) next larger cardinal).
We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:
:
:
: for an infinite limit ordinal
In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
,
The -th infinite initial ordinal is written . Its cardinality is written .
Informally, the aleph function is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals.
Formally, in ZFC, is ''not a function'', but a function-like class, as it is not a set (due to the Burali-Forti paradox).
Fixed points of omega
For any ordinal we have .
In many cases is strictly greater than ''α''. For example, it is true for any successor ordinal: holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence
:
which is sometimes denoted .
Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.[
] This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If were a successor ordinal, then would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible. If were a limit ordinal
In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
less than then its cofinality (and thus the cofinality of ) would be less than and so would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus and consequently which makes it a fixed point.
Role of axiom of choice
The cardinality of any infinite ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its initial ordinal. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well-order
In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then calle ...
able.
Each finite set
In mathematics, particularly set theory, a finite set is a set that has a finite number of elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example,
is a finite set with five elements. Th ...
is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.
Over ZF, the assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set
In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable.
Properties
The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.
When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as of minimum possible rank. This has the property that if and only if and have the same cardinality. (The set does not have the same cardinality of in general, but all its elements do.)
See also
* Beth number
* Gimel function
* Regular cardinal
* Infinity
Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is denoted by \infty, called the infinity symbol.
From the time of the Ancient Greek mathematics, ancient Greeks, the Infinity (philosophy), philosophic ...
* Transfinite number
In mathematics, transfinite numbers or infinite numbers are numbers that are " infinite" in the sense that they are larger than all finite numbers. These include the transfinite cardinals, which are cardinal numbers used to quantify the size of i ...
* Ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
Notes
References
External links
*
*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Aleph Number
Cardinal numbers
Hebrew alphabet
Infinity